94 Social Norms Essay Topic Ideas & Examples

🏆 best social norms topic ideas & essay examples, 📌 simple & easy social norms essay titles, 👍 good essay topics on social norms, ❓ questions about social norms.

  • Breaching Social Norms Experiment The struggle to violate a social norm and the sharp reaction to it is due to the culture that exists in that particular setting.
  • Social Norms in “A Streetcar Named Desire” by Tennessee Williams In Blanche’s opinion, beauty is the true value of a woman since it enables her to win recognition of men. The main tragedy of Blanche DuBois is that she was conditioned to act and behave […] We will write a custom essay specifically for you by our professional experts 808 writers online Learn More
  • Devil’s Playground: Social Norms and Rules of Morality It is the first step to the social chaos and decline which can be observed today in the youth’s alcohol and drugs abuse in spite of all the limitations. According to the Amish people’s visions, […]
  • Institutions, Social Norms and Rules in U.S. It is important to stress that the American Dream assumes a long-term type of life planning directly reflected in people’s actions and perceptions of society.
  • Departing From Social Norms Can Lead to Progress Following rules and social norms set by the community is like agreeing to the dictation of the superego. Fear is known to set boundaries and limit the abilities of people.
  • Creating Social Norms: Gender Depiction in Media Sources Among all types of information and misinformation presented in the media, the issue of gender roles is the most damaging of all.
  • Researching the Genetic Enhancement: Unethical Practice and Social Norms One of the challenges that have emerged with the advent of genetic enhancement is the inability to ensure that all people have access to the technology.
  • Social Norms as the Condition for Being Isolated The nature of changes can be traced in Othello who is treated as a person with different color of skin as well as Edna who is not accepted by the Creole community; Gregor Samsa is […]
  • Social Norms in ‘Bread Givers’ by Anzia Yezierska Sara is shocked at the turn of events and their mother is a mute spectator to her daughters’ miserable lives. The harsh realities of life have made her a mature woman, a Jewish woman of […]
  • Masculinity as a Social Norms Issue However, the advancements that occurred with the rise of the LGBT movement and the empowerment of women now challenge established ideas.
  • Breaching Social Norms Experiment and Analysis Additionally, there was a great relief that the experiment was over and I did not have to break social norms anymore.
  • Social Norms and Privacy Violation Online Being exposed to particular behaviors contributes to the concept of the norm, determines what people think they are expected to do, and can ultimately alter the behavior.
  • Deviant Law Concepts and Contraries to Social Norms Recently, I broke two norms when my uncle and I went to a movie in a movie theatre. After I had changed my pajamas for nice clothes, some of these people came to compliment me.
  • Effects of Media on Social Norms This paper aims to examine the influence of media on GCC’s citizens and international partners to determine ways in which it affects social norm changes.
  • Human Sexual Behavioral Ecology and Social Norms In the vast majority of cultures, females are regarded as major caregivers for their offspring while males may invest less time in the parental effort and spend more time searching for mates.
  • Breaking Social Norms in United Arab Emirates When I approached an Egyptian family, the mother required me to tell them the dish I wanted to taste and promised to order it for me.
  • Social Norms and Their Violations A more is a set of norms that promotes moral values in the society, the violation of which is fraught with dire consequences.
  • Public Policy vs. Social Norms and Corruption Political processes enshrined in democratic values of integrity and accountability must continue to shape the institutional framework in the region. Political and civil institutions in Sierra Leone could stop the escalation of illegal trade to […]
  • Voluntarily Separable Repeated Games with Social Norms
  • The Social Norms of Feminine Appearance in Advertisements
  • The Social Norms And Attitudes Of Dating And Courtship
  • The Social Status and Adherence of Characters to Social Norms in Sense and Sensibility, a Novel by Jane Austen
  • The Relationship between Social Norms and Tax Compliance: The Moderating Role of the Effectiveness of Tax Administration
  • The Social Norms and Their Effects on Society and Human Behavior
  • The Minnesota Income Tax Compliance Experiment: Replication of the Social Norms Experiment
  • The Evolution of Social Norms in Common Property Resource Use
  • Total Strangers and the Social Norms of Our Culture
  • The Social Norms of Tax Compliance: Evidence from Australia, Singapore, and the United States
  • The Violation of Athenian Social Norms and Lysistrata by Aristophanes
  • The Criminal Law Is Shaped By The Social Norms And Traditions
  • The Friendship Paradox and Systematic Biases in Perceptions and Social Norms
  • The Importance of Parental Knowledge and Social Norms: Evidence from Weight Report Cards in Mexico
  • The Definitions of Abnormality: Deviation from Social Norms and Ideal Mental Health
  • The Influence of Social Norms on Gender Inequality
  • The Spirit of the Law over its Letter: The Role of Culture and Social Norms in Shielding Cooperative Banks from Systemic Shocks
  • Society Is Influenced By Social Norms That Guides Our Everyday Behavior
  • Work Ethic: Influenced By Learned Culture and Social Norms
  • Symbols, Signals, and Social Norms in Politics and the Law
  • Why do People Punish the Rule Breakers?: The Sustainability of Social Norms
  • The Use of Power, Influence, and Social Norms in Keeping the Idea of Slavery Alive by the United States Government
  • Strong Reciprocity, Human Cooperation, and the Enforcement of Social Norms
  • The Emergence and Effects of Social Norms: A Confrontation of Some Hypotheses of Sociology and Economics
  • The Significant Impact of Technology and Social Media on the Evolution of Social Norms
  • The Impact of Social Norms on Science and History
  • The Underground Labor Market between Social Norms and Economic Incentives
  • Themes of Personal Responsibility, Heroism, Social Norms
  • What Are the Social Norms Inside a Laundromat
  • Spatial Evolution of Social Norms in a Common-Pool Resource Game
  • The Influence of Alcohol Advertisements on Social Norms
  • Spillover Effects in Healthcare Programs: Evidence on Social Norms and Information Sharing
  • What Were The Social Norms Of This Consumer Culture?
  • Tax Compliance Social Norms and Institutional Quality: An Evolutionary Theory of Public Good Provision
  • What Kind Of Social Norms Do Other Cultures Have?
  • The Determinants of Misreporting Weight and Height: The Role of Social Norms
  • Using Social Norms Interventions For Reducing Adolescent
  • The Impact Of Social Norms On American Society
  • The Inevitable Outcome Of Fighting Social Norms
  • The Role of Social Norms in Child Labor and Schooling in India
  • The Wage Effects of Social Norms – Evidence of Deviations from Peers’ Body Mass in Europe
  • Social Norms: The Fundamental Building Blocks Of Sociology
  • The Relevance of Social Norms for Economic Efficiency: Theory and its Empirical Test
  • Social Norms, Status Spending, and Household Debt: Evidence from Kyrgyzstan
  • Stability Criteria for Social Norms with Applications to the Prisoner’s Dilemma
  • Tax Law and Social Norms in Mandatory Palestine and Israel
  • How Durable Are Social Norms?
  • Why Most People Tend to Conform in Most of Their Social Interactions, While Others Deviate From the Existing Social Norms?
  • Can Contracts Signal Social Norms?
  • How Is Breaking Social Norms Understood as Deviant Behavior?
  • Can Economic Pressure Overcome Social Norms?
  • How Have Cellphones Impacted Social Norms?
  • Can Social Norms Affect the International Allocation of Innovation?
  • How Do Delinquents Violate Social Norms and Still Maintain Positive Self-Image?
  • What Are the Types of Social Norms?
  • How Do Individual Habits Fit or Unfit Social Norms?
  • What Are the Social Norms Inside a Laundromat?
  • How Does Police Deviance Affect Many Social Norms?
  • What Sustains Social Norms and How They Evolve?
  • How Do Social Norms Influence Our Behavior?
  • What Were the Social Norms of the Consumer Culture?
  • How Must Social Norms Be Increased From the Feedback Loop?
  • When Do Social Norms and Self-Image Conflict?
  • How Do Social Norms Transform as a Result of the Information Age?
  • Why Do Juveniles Deviate From Social Norms?
  • How Societies Construct Social Norms?
  • Are Social Norms a Form of Oppression or a Necessity?
  • How Do Social Norms Affect Mental Health?
  • What Is the Importance of Social Norms in Society?
  • How Do Social Norms Affect Society?
  • What Is the Problem With Social Norms?
  • How Do Social Norms Help Keep Our Society Functioning?
  • What Would Life Be Like Without Social Norms?
  • How Can Social Norms Change?
  • What Violates Social Norms Concerning Right and Wrong?
  • How Do Norms Affect Our Identity?
  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2024, February 29). 94 Social Norms Essay Topic Ideas & Examples. https://ivypanda.com/essays/topic/social-norms-essay-topics/

"94 Social Norms Essay Topic Ideas & Examples." IvyPanda , 29 Feb. 2024, ivypanda.com/essays/topic/social-norms-essay-topics/.

IvyPanda . (2024) '94 Social Norms Essay Topic Ideas & Examples'. 29 February.

IvyPanda . 2024. "94 Social Norms Essay Topic Ideas & Examples." February 29, 2024. https://ivypanda.com/essays/topic/social-norms-essay-topics/.

1. IvyPanda . "94 Social Norms Essay Topic Ideas & Examples." February 29, 2024. https://ivypanda.com/essays/topic/social-norms-essay-topics/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "94 Social Norms Essay Topic Ideas & Examples." February 29, 2024. https://ivypanda.com/essays/topic/social-norms-essay-topics/.

  • Social Problems Essay Ideas
  • Relationship Research Ideas
  • Socialization Essay Ideas
  • Morality Research Ideas
  • Gender Equality Questions
  • Human Rights Essay Ideas
  • Parenting Research Topics
  • Human Nature Essay Titles
  • Personality Development Ideas
  • Psychology Questions
  • Social Democracy Essay Titles
  • Public Safety Research Ideas
  • Consumerism Topics
  • Racism Paper Topics
  • Culture Topics

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Social Norms

Social norms, the informal rules that govern behavior in groups and societies, have been extensively studied in the social sciences. Anthropologists have described how social norms function in different cultures (Geertz 1973), sociologists have focused on their social functions and how they motivate people to act (Durkheim 1895 [1982], 1950 [1957]; Parsons 1937; Parsons & Shils 1951; James Coleman 1990; Hechter & Opp 2001), and economists have explored how adherence to norms influences market behavior (Akerlof 1976; Young 1998a). More recently, also legal scholars have touted social norms as efficient alternatives to legal rules, as they may internalize negative externalities and provide signaling mechanisms at little or no cost (Ellickson 1991; Posner 2000).

With a few exceptions, the social science literature conceives of norms as exogenous variables. Since norms are mainly seen as constraining behavior, some of the key differences between moral, social, and legal norms—as well as differences between norms and conventions—have been blurred. Much attention has instead been paid to the conditions under which norms will be obeyed. Because of that, the issue of sanctions has been paramount in the social science literature. Moreover, since social norms are seen as central to the production of social order or social coordination, research on norms has been focused on the functions they perform. Yet even if a norm may fulfill important social functions (such as welfare maximization or the elimination of externalities), it cannot be explained solely on the basis of the functions it performs. The simplistic functionalist perspective has been rejected on several accounts; in fact, even though a given norm can be conceived as a means to achieve some goal, this is usually not the reason why it emerged in the first place (Elster 1989a, 1989b). Moreover, although a particular norm may persist (as opposed to emerge) because of some positive social function it fulfills, there are many others that are inefficient and even widely unpopular.

Philosophers have taken a different approach to norms. In the literature on norms and conventions, both social constructs are seen as the endogenous product of individuals’ interactions (Lewis 1969; Ullmann-Margalit 1977; Vandershraaf 1995; Bicchieri 2006). Norms are represented as equilibria of games of strategy, and as such they are supported by a cluster of self-fulfilling expectations. Beliefs, expectations, group knowledge and common knowledge have thus become central concepts in the development of a philosophical view of social norms. Paying attention to the role played by expectations in supporting social norms has helped differentiate between social norms, conventions, and descriptive norms: an important distinction often overlooked in the social science accounts, but crucial when we need to diagnose the nature of a pattern of behavior in order to intervene on it.

1. General Issues

2. early theories: socialization, 3. early theories: social identity, 4. early theories: cost-benefit models, 5. game-theoretic accounts, 6. experimental evidence, 7. evolutionary models, 8. conclusion, other internet resources, related entries.

Social norms, like many other social phenomena, are the unplanned result of individuals’ interaction. It has been argued that social norms ought to be understood as a kind of grammar of social interactions. Like a grammar, a system of norms specifies what is acceptable and what is not in a society or group. And, analogously to a grammar, it is not the product of human design. This view suggests that a study of the conditions under which norms come into being—as opposed to one stressing the functions fulfilled by social norms—is important to understand the differences between social norms and other types of injunction (such as hypothetical imperatives, moral codes, or legal rules).

Another important issue often blurred in the literature on norms is the relationship between normative beliefs and behavior. Some authors identify norms with observable, recurrent patterns of behavior. Others only focus on normative beliefs and expectations. Such accounts find it difficult to explain the complexity and heterogeneity of norm-driven behaviors, as they offer an explanation of conformity that is at best partial.

Some popular accounts of why social norms exist are the following. Norms are efficient means to achieve social welfare (Arrow 1971; Akerlof 1976), prevent market failures (Jules Coleman 1989), or cut social costs (Thibaut & Kelley 1959; Homans 1961); norms are either Nash equilibria of coordination games or cooperative equilibria of prisoner’s dilemma-type games (Lewis 1969; Ullmann-Margalit 1977), and as such they solve collective action problems.

Akerlof’s (1976) analysis of the norms that regulate land systems is a good example of the tenet that “norms are efficient means to achieve social welfare”. Since the worker is much poorer and less liquid than the landlord, it would be more natural for the landlord rather than the tenant to bear the risk of crop failure. This would be the case if the landlord kept all the crops, and paid the worker a wage (i.e., the case of a “wage system”). Since the wage would not directly depend on the worker’s effort, this system leaves no incentive to the worker for any effort beyond the minimum necessary. In sharecropping, on the contrary, the worker is paid both for the effort and the time he puts in: a more efficient arrangement in that it increases production.

Thibaut and Kelley’s (1959) view of norms as substitutes for informal influence has a similar functionalist flavor. As an example, they consider a repeated battle of the sexes game. In this game, some bargaining is necessary for each party to obtain, at least occasionally, the preferred outcome. The parties can engage in a costly sequence of threats and promises, but it seems better to agree beforehand on a rule of behavior, such as alternating between the respectively preferred outcomes. Rules emerge because they reduce the costs involved in face-to-face personal influence.

Likewise, Ullman-Margalit (1977) uses game theory to show that norms solve collective action problems, such as prisoner’s dilemma-type situations; in her own words, “… a norm solving the problem inherent in a situation of this type is generated by it” (1977: 22). In a collective action problem, self-centered rational choices produce a Pareto-inefficient outcome. Pareto-efficiency is restored by means of norms backed by sanctions. James Coleman (1990), too, believes that norms emerge in situations in which there are externalities, that is, in all those cases in which an activity produces negative (positive) effects on other parties, without this being reflected in direct compensation; thus the producer of the externality pays no cost for (reaps no benefit from) the unintended effect of their activity. A norm solves the problem by regulating the externality-producing activity, introducing a system of sanctions (rewards).

Also Brennan, Eriksson, Goodin, and Southwood (2013) argue that norms have a function. Norms function to hold us accountable to each other for adherence to the principles that they cover. This may or may not create effective coordination over any given principle, but they place us in positions where we may praise and blame people for their behaviors and attitudes. This function of accountability, they argue, can help create another role for norms, which is imbuing practices with social meaning. This social meaning arises from the expectations that we can place on each other for compliance, and the fact that those behaviors can come to represent shared values, and even a sense of shared identity. This functional role of norms separates it from bare social practices or even common sets of desires, as those non-normative behaviors don’t carry with them the social accountability that is inherent in norms. The distinctive feature of the Brennan et al. account of norms is the centrality of accountability: this feature is what distinguishes norms from other social practices.

All of the above are examples of a functionalist explanation of norms. Functionalist accounts are sometimes criticized for offering a post hoc justification for the existence of norms (i.e., the mere presence of a norm does not justify inferring that that norm exists to accomplish some social function). Indeed, a purely functionalist view may not account for the fact that many social norms are harmful or inefficient (e.g., discriminatory norms against women and minorities), or are so rigid as to prevent the fine-tuning that would be necessary to accommodate new cases. There, one would expect increasing social pressure to abandon such norms.

According to some authors, we can explain the emergence of norms without any reference to the functions they eventually come to perform. Since the norms that are most interesting to study are those that emerge naturally from individuals’ interactions (Schelling 1978), an important theoretical task is to analyze the conditions under which such norms come into being. Because norms often provide a solution to the problem of maintaining social order—and social order requires cooperation—many studies on the emergence and dynamics of norms have focused on cooperation. Norms of honesty, loyalty, reciprocity and promise-keeping are indeed important to the smooth functioning of social groups. One hypothesis is that such cooperative norms emerge in close-knit groups where people have ongoing interactions with each other (Hardin 1982). Evolutionary game theory provides a useful framework for investigating this hypothesis, since repeated games serve as a simple approximation of life in a close-knit group (Axelrod 1984, 1986; Skyrms 1996; Gintis 2000). In repeated encounters people have an opportunity to learn from each other’s behavior, and to secure a pattern of reciprocity that minimizes the likelihood of misperception. In this regard, it has been argued that the cooperative norms likely to develop in close-knit groups are simple ones (Alexander 2000, 2005, 2007); in fact, delayed and disproportionate punishment, as well as belated rewards, are often difficult to understand and hence ineffective. Although norms originate in small, close-knit groups, they often spread well beyond the narrow boundaries of the original group. The challenge thus becomes one of explaining the dynamics of the norm propagation from small groups to large populations.

If norms can thrive and spread, they can also die out. A poorly understood phenomenon is the sudden and unexpected change of well-established patterns of behavior. For example, smoking in public without asking for permission has become unacceptable, and only a few years ago nobody would have worried about using gender-laden language. One would expect inefficient norms (such as discriminatory norms against women and minorities) to disappear more rapidly and with greater frequency than more efficient norms. However, Bicchieri (2016) points out that inefficiency is not a sufficient condition for a norm’s demise. This can be seen by the study of crime and corruption: corruption results in huge social costs, but such costs—even when they take a society to the brink of collapse—are not enough to generate an overhaul of the system. Muldoon (2018a, 2018b, 2020) has argued that social norms are a challenging form of social regulation precisely because there is no simple way to intentionally modify a social norm, as one can with a law or institutional rule. Social norms can even shape one's understanding of how much agency one has (Muldoon 2017).

An influential view of norms considers them as clusters of self-fulfilling expectations (Schelling 1960), in that some expectations often result in behavior that reinforces them. A related view emphasizes the importance of conditional preferences in supporting social norms (Sugden 2000). In particular, according to Bicchieri’s (2006) account, preferences for conformity to social norms are conditional on “empirical expectations” (i.e., first-order beliefs that a certain behavior will be followed) as well as “normative expectations” (i.e., second-order beliefs that a certain behavior ought to be followed). Thus, norm compliance results from the joint presence of a conditional preference for conformity and the belief that other people will conform as well as approve of conformity.

Note that characterizing norms simply as clusters of expectations might be misleading; similarly, a norm cannot simply be identified with a recurrent behavioral pattern either. If we were to adopt a purely behavioral account of norms there would be no way to distinguish shared rules of fairness from, say, the collective morning habit of tooth brushing. After all, such a practice does not depend on whether one expects others to do the same; however, one would not even try to ask for a salary proportionate to one’s education, if one expected compensation to merely follow a seniority rule. In fact, there are behavioral patterns that can only be explained by the existence of norms, even if the behavior prescribed by the norm in question is currently unobserved. For example, in a study of the Ik people, Turnbull (1972) reported that starved hunters-gatherers tried hard to avoid situations where their compliance with norms of reciprocity was expected. Thus they would go out of their way not to be in the position of gift-taker, and hunted alone so that they would not be forced to share their prey with anyone else. Much of the Ik’s behavior could be explained as a way of eluding existing reciprocity norms.

There are many other instances of discrepancies between expectations and behavior . For example, it is remarkable to observe how often people expect others to act selfishly, even when they are prepared to act altruistically themselves (Miller & Ratner 1996). Studies have shown that people’s willingness to give blood is not altered by monetary incentives, but typically those very people who are willing to donate blood for free expect others to donate blood only in the presence of monetary rewards. Similarly, all the interviewed landlords answered positively to a question about whether they would rent an apartment to an unmarried couple; however, they estimated that only 50% of other landlords would accept unmarried couples as tenants (Dawes 1972). Such cases of pluralistic ignorance are rather common; what is puzzling is that people may expect a given norm to be upheld in the face of personal evidence to the contrary (Bicchieri & Fukui 1999). Furthermore, there is evidence suggesting that people who donate blood, tip on a foreign trip, give money to beggars or return a lost wallet often attempt to downplay their altruistic behavior (by supplying selfish motives that seemingly align their actions with a norm of self-interest; Wuthnow 1991, 77).

In a nutshell, norms refer to actions over which people have control, and are supported by shared expectations about what should or should not be done in different types of social situations. However, norms cannot be identified just with observable behavior, nor can they merely be equated with normative beliefs.

The varying degrees of correlation between normative beliefs and actions are an important factor researchers can use to differentiate among various types of norms. Such a correlation is also a key element to consider when critically assessing competing theories of norms: we begin by surveying the socialized actor theory, the social identity theory, and some early rational choice (cost-benefit) models of conformity.

In the theory of the socialized actor (Parsons 1951), individual action is intended as a choice among alternatives. Human action is understood within a utilitarian framework as instrumentally oriented and utility maximizing. Although a utilitarian setting does not necessarily imply a view of human motives as essentially egoistic, this is the preferred interpretation of utilitarianism adopted by Talcott Parsons and much contemporary sociology. In this context, it becomes crucial to explain through which mechanisms social order and stability are attained in a society that would otherwise be in a permanent Hobbesian state of nature. In short, order and stability are essentially socially derived phenomena, brought about by a common value system —the “cement” of society. The common values of a society are embodied in norms that, when conformed to, guarantee the orderly functioning and reproduction of the social system. In the Parsonian framework norms are exogenous: how such a common value system is created and how it may change are issues left unexplored. The most important question is rather how norms get to be followed, and what prompts rational egoists to abide by them. The answer given by the theory of the socialized actor is that people voluntarily adhere to the shared value system, because it is introjected to form a constitutive element of the personality itself (Parsons 1951).

In Parsons’ own words, a norm is

a verbal description of a concrete course of action, … , regarded as desirable, combined with an injunction to make certain future actions conform to this course. (1937: 75)

Norms play a crucial role in individual choice since—by shaping individual needs and preferences—they serve as criteria for selecting among alternatives. Such criteria are shared by a given community and embody a common value system. People may choose what they prefer, but what they prefer in turn conforms to social expectations: norms influence behavior because, through a process of socialization that starts in infancy, they become part of one’s motives for action. Conformity to standing norms is a stable, acquired disposition that is independent of the consequences of conforming. Such lasting dispositions are formed by long-term interactions with significant others (e.g., one’s parents): through repeated socialization, individuals come to learn and internalize the common values embodied in the norms. Internalization is conceived as the process by which people develop a psychological need or motive to conform to a set of shared norms. When norms are internalized norm-abiding behavior will be perceived as good or appropriate, and people will typically feel guilt or shame at the prospect of behaving in a deviant way. If internalization is successful external sanctions will play no role in eliciting conformity and, since individuals are motivated to conform, it follows that normative beliefs and actions will be consistent.

Although Parsons’ analysis of social systems starts with a theory of individual action, he views social actors as behaving according to roles that define their identities and actions (through socialization and internalization). The goal of individual action is to maximize satisfaction. The potential conflict between individual desires and collective goals is resolved by characterizing the common value system as one that precedes and constrains the social actor. The price of this solution is the disappearance of the individual actor as the basic unit of analysis. Insofar as individuals are role-bearers, in Parsons’ theory it is social entities that act: entities that are completely detached from the individual actions that created them. This consideration forms the basis for most of the criticisms raised against the theory of the socialized actor (Wrong 1961); such criticisms are typically somewhat abstract as they are cast in the framework of the holism/individualism controversy.

On the other hand, one may easily verify whether empirical predictions drawn from the socialized actor theory are supported by experimental evidence. For instance, the following predictions can be derived from the theory and easily put to test. (a) Norms will change very slowly and only through intensive social interaction. (b) Normative beliefs are positively correlated to actions; whenever such beliefs change, behavior will follow. (c) If a norm is successfully internalized, expectations of others’ conformity will have no effect on an individual’s choice to conform.

Some of the above statements are not supported by empirical evidence from social psychology. For example, it has been shown that there may not be a relation between people’s normative beliefs (or attitudes) and what people in fact do. In this respect, it should be noted that experimental psychologists have generally focused on “attitudes”, that is, “evaluative feelings of pro or con, favorable or unfavorable, with regard to particular objects” (where the objects may be “concrete representations of things or actions, or abstract concepts”; Insko & Schopler 1967: 361–362). As such, the concept of attitude is quite broad: it includes normative beliefs, as well as personal opinions and preferences. That said, a series of field experiments has provided evidence contrary to the assumption that attitudes and behaviors are closely related. LaPiere (1934) famously reported a sharp divergence between the widespread anti-Chinese attitudes in the United States and the tolerant behavior he witnessed. Other studies have pointed to inconsistencies between an individual’s stated normative beliefs and her actions (Wicker 1969): several reasons may account for such a discrepancy. For example, studies of racial prejudice indicate that normative beliefs are more likely to determine behavior in long-lasting relationships, and least likely to determine behavior in the transient situations typical of experimental studies (Harding et al. 1954 [1969]; Gaertner & Dovidio 1986). Warner and DeFleur (1969) reported that the main variable affecting discriminatory behavior is one’s belief about what society (e.g., most other people) says one should do, as opposed to what one personally thinks one should do.

In brief, the social psychology literature provides mixed evidence in support of the claim that an individual’s normative beliefs and attitudes influence her actions. Such studies, however, do not carefully discriminate among various types of normative beliefs. In particular, one should distinguish between “personal normative beliefs” (i.e., beliefs that a certain behavior ought to be followed) and “normative expectations” (i.e., what one believes others believe ought to be done, that is, a second-order belief): it then becomes apparent that oftentimes only such second-order beliefs affect behavior.

The above constitutes an important criticism of the socialized actor theory. According to Parsons, once a norm is internalized, members of society are motivated to conform by an internal sanctioning system; therefore, one should observe a high correlation among all orders of normative beliefs and behavior. However, experimental evidence does not support such a view (see also: Fishbein 1967; Cialdini et al. 1991). Another indication that the socialized actor theory lacks generality is the observation that norms can change rather quickly, and that new norms often emerge in a short period of time among complete strangers (Mackie 1996). Long-term or close interactions do not seem to be necessary for someone to acquire a given normative disposition, as is testified by the relative ease with which individuals learn new norms when they change status or group (e.g., from single to married, from student to faculty, etc.). Moreover, studies of emergent social and political groups have shown that new norms may form rather rapidly, and that the demise of old patterns of behavior is often abrupt (Robinson 1932; Klassen et al. 1989; Prentice & Miller 1993; Matza 1964). Given the aforementioned limitations, Parsons’ theory might perhaps be taken as an explanation of a particular conception of moral norms (in the sense of internalized, unconditional imperatives), but it cannot be viewed as a general theory of social norms.

It has been argued that behavior is often closely embedded in a network of personal relations, and that a theory of norms should not leave the specific social context out of consideration (Granovetter 1985). Critics of the socialized actor theory have called for an alternative conception of norms that may account for the often weak relation between beliefs and behavior (Deutscher 1973). This alternative approach takes social relations to be crucial in explaining social action, and considers social identity as a key motivating factor. (A strong support for this view among anthropologists is to be found in the work of Cancian 1975.)

Since the notion of social identity is inextricably linked to that of group behavior, it is important to clarify the relation between these concepts. By “social identity” we refer, in Tajfel’s own words, to

that part of an individual’s self-concept which derives from his knowledge of his membership of a social group (or groups) together with the value and emotional significance attached to that membership. (Tajfel 1981: 255)

Note that a crucial feature of social identity is that one’s identification with the group is in some sense a conscious choice: one may accidentally belong to a group, but we can meaningfully talk of social identification only when being a group-member becomes (at least in part) constitutive of who one is. According to Tajfel’s theory, when we categorize ourselves as belonging to a particular group, the perception and definition of the self—as well as our motives—change. That is, we start perceiving ourselves and our fellow group-members along impersonal, “typical” dimensions that characterize the group to which we belong. Such dimensions include specific roles and the beliefs (or actions) that accompany them.

Turner et al.’s (1987) “self-categorization theory” provides a more specific characterization of self-perception, or self-definition, as a system of cognitive self-schemata that filter and process information. Such schemata result in a representation of the social situation that guides the choice of appropriate action. This system has at least two major components, i.e., social and personal identity. Social identity refers to self-descriptions related to group memberships. Personal identity refers to self-descriptions such as individual character traits, abilities, and tastes. Although personal and social identities are mutually exclusive levels of self-definition, this distinction must be taken as an approximation (in that there are many interconnections between social and personal identities). It is, however, important to recognize that we often perceive ourselves primarily in terms of our relevant group memberships rather than as differentiated, unique individuals. So—depending on the situation—personal or group identity will become salient (Brewer 1991).

For example, when one makes interpersonal comparisons between oneself and other group-members, personal identity will become salient; instead, group identity will become salient in situations in which one’s group is compared to another group. Within a group, all those factors that lead members to categorize themselves as different (or endowed with special characteristics and traits) will enhance personal identity. If a group has to solve a common task, but each member is to be rewarded according to her contribution, personal abilities are highlighted and individuals will perceive themselves as unique and different from the rest of the group. Conversely, if all group-members are to equally share the reward for a jointly performed task, group identification will be enhanced. When the difference between self and fellow group-members is accentuated, we are likely to observe selfish motives and self-favoritism against other group-members. When instead group identification is enhanced, in-group favoritism against out-group members will be activated, as well as behavior contrary to self-interest.

According to Turner, social identity is basically a cognitive mechanism whose adaptive function is to make “group behavior” possible. Whenever social identification becomes salient, a cognitive mechanism of categorization is activated in such a way to produce perceptual and behavioral changes. Such categorization is called a stereotype, the prototypical description of what members of a given category are (or are believed to be). It is a cluster of physical, mental and psychological characteristics attributed to a “typical” member of a given group. Stereotyping, like any other categorization process, activates scripts or schemata, and what we call group behavior is nothing but scripted behavior. For example, the category “Asian student” is associated with a cluster of behaviors, personality traits, and values: we often think of Asian students as respectful, diligent, disciplined, and especially good with technical subjects. When thinking of an Asian student solely in terms of group membership, we attribute her the stereotypical characteristics associated with her group, so she becomes interchangeable with other group-members. When we perceive people in terms of stereotypes, we depersonalize them and see them as “typical” members of their group. The same process is at work when we perceive ourselves as group-members: self-stereotyping is a cognitive shift from “perceiving oneself as unique” to “perceiving oneself in terms of the attributes that characterize the group”. It is this cognitive shift that mediates group behavior.

Group behavior (as opposed to individual behavior) is characterized by features such as a perceived similarity between group-members, cohesiveness, a tendency to cooperate to achieve common goals, shared attitudes or beliefs, and conformity to group norms. Once an individual self-categorizes as member of a group, she will perceive herself as “depersonalized” and similar to other group-members in the relevant stereotypical dimensions. Insofar as group-members perceive their interests and goals as identical—because such interests and goals are stereotypical attributes of the group—self-stereotyping will induce a group-member to embrace such interests and goals as her own. It is thus predicted that pro-social behavior will be enhanced by group membership, and diluted when people act in an individualistic mode (Brewer 1979).

The groups with which we happen to identify ourselves may be very large (as in the case in which one self-defines as Muslim or French), or as small as a friends’ group. Some general group identities may not involve specific norms, but there are many cases in which group identification and social norms are inextricably connected. In that case group-members believe that certain patterns of behavior are unique to them, and use their distinctive norms to define group membership. Many close-knit groups (such as the Amish or the Hasidic Jews) enforce norms of separation proscribing marriage with outsiders, as well as specific dress codes and a host of other prescriptive and proscriptive norms. There, once an individual perceives herself as a group-member, she will adhere to the group prototype and behave in accordance with it. Hogg and Turner (1987) have called the process through which individuals come to conform to group norms “referent informational influence”.

Group-specific norms have (among other things) the twofold function of minimizing perceived differences among group-members and maximizing differences between the group and outsiders. Once formed, such norms become stable cognitive representations of appropriate behavior as a group-member. Social identity is built around group characteristics and behavioral standards, and hence any perceived lack of conformity to group norms is seen as a threat to the legitimacy of the group. Self-categorization accentuates the similarities between one’s behavior and that prescribed by the group norm, thus causing conformity as well as the disposition to control and punish transgressors. In the social identity framework, group norms are obeyed because one identifies with the group, and conformity is mediated by self-categorization as an in-group member. A telling historical example of the relationship between norms and group membership was the division of England into the two parties of the Roundheads and Cavaliers. Charles Mackay reports that

in those days every species of vice and iniquity was thought by the Puritans to lurk in the long curly tresses of the monarchists, while the latter imagined that their opponents were as destitute of wit, of wisdom, and of virtue, as they were of hair. A man’s locks were a symbol of his creed, both in politics and religion. The more abundant the hair, the more scant the faith; and the balder the head, the more sincere the piety. (Mackay 1841: 351)

It should be noted that in this framework social norms are defined by collective—as opposed to personal—beliefs about appropriate behaviors (Homans 1950, 1961). To a certain extent, this characterization of social norms is closer to recent accounts than it is to Parsons’ socialized actor theory. On the other hand, a distinct feature of the social identity framework is that people’s motivation to conform comes from their desire to validate their identity as group-members. In short, there are several empirical predictions one can draw from such a framework. Given the theory’s emphasis on identity as a motivating factor, conformity to a norm is not assumed to depend on an individual’s internalization of that norm; in fact, a change in social status or group membership will bring about a change in the norms relevant to the new status/group. Thus a new norm can be quickly adopted without much interaction, and beliefs about identity validation may change very rapidly under the pressure of external circumstances. In this case, not just norm compliance, but norms themselves are potentially unstable.

The experimental literature on social dilemmas has utilized the “priming of group identity” as a mechanism for promoting cooperative behavior (Dawes 1980; Brewer & Schneider 1990). The typical hypothesis is that a pre-play, face-to-face communication stage may induce identification with the group, and thus promote cooperative behavior among group-members. In effect, rates of cooperation have been shown to be generally higher in social dilemma experiments preceded by a pre-play communication stage (Dawes 1991). However, it has been argued that face-to-face communication may actually help group-members gather relevant information about one another: such information may therefore induce subjects to trust each other’s promises and act cooperatively, regardless of any group identification. In this respect, it has been shown that communication per se does not foster cooperation, unless subjects are allowed to talk about relevant topics (Bicchieri & Lev-On 2007). This provides support for the view that communication does not enhance cohesion but rather focuses subjects on relevant rules of behavior, which do not necessarily depend on group identification.

Cooperative outcomes can thus be explained without resorting to the concept of social identity. A social identity explanation appears to be more appropriate in the context of a relatively stable environment, where individuals have had time to make emotional investments (or at least can expect repeated future interactions within the same group). In artificial lab settings, where there are no expectations of future interactions, the concept of social identity seems less persuasive as an explanation of the observed rates of cooperation. On the other hand, we note that social identity does appear to play a role in experimental settings in which participants are divided into separate groups. (In that case, it has been shown that participants categorize the situation as “we versus them”, activating in-group loyalty and trust, and an equal degree of mistrust toward the out-group; Kramer & Brewer 1984; Bornstein & Ben-Yossef 1994.)

Even with stable environments and repeated interactions, however, a theory of norm compliance in terms of social identity cannot avoid the difficulty of making predictions when one is simultaneously committed to different identities. We may concurrently be workers, parents, spouses, friends, club members, and party affiliates, to name but a few of the possible identities we embrace. For each of them there are rules that define what is appropriate, acceptable, or good behavior. In the social identity framework, however, it is not clear what happens when one is committed to different identities that may involve conflicting behaviors.

Finally, there is ample evidence that people’s perceptions may change very rapidly. Since in this framework norms are defined as shared perceptions about group beliefs, one would expect that—whenever all members of a group happen to believe that others have changed their beliefs about core membership rules—the very norms that define membership will change. The study of fashion, fads and speculative bubbles clearly shows that there are some domains in which rapid (and possibly disruptive) changes of collective expectations may occur; it is, however, much less clear what sort of norms are more likely to be subject to rapid changes (think of dress codes rather than codes of honor). The social identity view does not offer a theoretical framework for differentiating these cases: although some norms are indeed related to group membership, and thus compliance may be explained through identity-validation mechanisms, there appear to be limits to the social identity explanation.

Early rational choice models of conformity maintained that, since norms are upheld by sanctions, compliance is merely a payoff-maximizing strategy (Rommetveit 1955; Thibaut & Kelley 1959): when others’ approval and disapproval act as external sanctions, we have a “cost-benefit model” of compliance (Axelrod 1986; James Coleman 1990). Rule-complying strategies are rationally chosen in order to avoid negative sanctions or to attract positive sanctions. This class of rational choice models defines norms behaviorally, equating them with patterns of behavior (while disregarding expectations or values). Such approach relies heavily on sanctions as a motivating factor. According to Axelrod (1986), for example, if we observe individuals to follow a regular pattern of behavior and to be punished if they act otherwise, then we have a norm. Similarly, Coleman (1990) argues that a norm coincides with a set of sanctions that act to direct a given behavior.

However, it has been shown that not all social norms involve sanctions (Diamond 1935; Hoebel 1954). Moreover, sanctioning works generally well in small groups and in the context of repeated interactions, where the identity of participants is known and monitoring is relatively easy. Still, even in such cases there may be a so-called second-order public goods problem. That is, imposing negative sanctions on transgressors is in everybody’s interest, but the individual who observes a transgression faces a dilemma: she is to decide whether or not to punish the transgressor, where punishing typically involves costs; besides, there is no guarantee that other individuals will also impose a penalty on transgressors when faced with the same dilemma. An answer to this problem has been to assume that there exist “meta-norms” that tell people to punish transgressors of lower-level norms (Axelrod 1986). This solution, however, only shifts the problem one level up: upholding the meta-norm itself requires the existence of a higher-level sanctioning system.

Another problem with sanctions is the following: a sanction, to be effective, must be recognized as such. Coleman and Axelrod typically take the repeated prisoner’s dilemma game as an example of the working of sanctions. However, in a repeated prisoner’s dilemma the same action (“C” or “D”) must serve as both the sanctioning action and the target action. By simply looking at behavior, it is unclear whether the action is a function of a sanction or a sanction itself. It thus becomes difficult to determine the presence of a norm, or to assess its effect on choice as distinct from the individual strategies of players.

A further consideration weakens the credibility of the view that norms are upheld only because of external sanctions. Often we keep conforming to a norm even in situations of complete anonymity, where the probability of being caught transgressing is almost zero. In this case fear of sanctions cannot be a motivating force. As a consequence, it is often argued that cases of “spontaneous” compliance are the result of internalization (Scott 1971): people who have developed an internal sanctioning system feel guilt and shame at behaving in a deviant way. Yet, we have seen that the Parsonian view of internalization and socialization is inadequate, as it leads to predictions about compliance that often run counter to empirical evidence.

In particular, James Coleman (1990) has argued in favor of reducing internalization to rational choice, insofar as it is in the interest of a group to get another group to internalize certain norms. In this case internalization would still be the result of some form of socialization. This theory faces some of the same objections raised against Parsons’ theory: norms that are passed on from parents to children, for example, should be extremely resistant to change; hence, one should expect a high degree of correlation between such norms and behavior, especially in those cases where norms prescribe specific kinds of actions. However, studies of normative beliefs about honesty—which one typically acquires during childhood—show that such beliefs are often uncorrelated with behavior (Freeman & Ataöv 1960).

Bicchieri (1990, 1997) has presented a third, alternative view about internalization. This view of internalization is cognitive, and is grounded on the assumption that social norms develop in small, close-knit groups where ongoing interactions are the rule. Once an individual has learned to behave in a way consistent with the group’s interests, she will tend to persist in the learned behavior unless it becomes clear that—on average—the cost of upholding the norm significantly outweighs the benefits. Small groups can typically monitor their members’ behavior and successfully employ retaliation whenever free-riding is observed. In such groups an individual will learn, maybe at some personal cost, to cooperate; she will then uphold the cooperative norm as a “default rule” in any new encounter, unless it becomes evident that the cost of conformity has become excessive. The idea that norms may be “sluggish” is in line with well-known results from cognitive psychology showing that, once a norm has emerged in a group, it will tend to guide the behavior of its members even when they face a new situation (or are isolated from the original group; Sherif 1936).

Empirical evidence shows that norm-abiding behavior is not, as the early rational choice models would have it, a matter of cost/benefit calculation. Upholding a norm that has led one to fare reasonably well in the past is a way of economizing on the effort one would have to exert to devise a strategy when facing a new situation . This kind of “bounded rationality” approach explains why people tend to obey norms that sometimes put them at a disadvantage, as is the case with norms of honesty. This does not mean, however, that external sanctions never play a role in compliance: for example, in the initial development of a norm sanctions may indeed play an important role. Yet, once a norm is established, there are several mechanisms that may account for conformity.

Finally, the view that one conforms only because of the threat of negative sanctions does not distinguish norm-abiding behavior from an obsession or an entrenched habit; nor does that view distinguish social norms from hypothetical imperatives enforced by sanctions (such as the rule that prohibits naked sunbathing on public beaches). In these cases avoidance of the sanctions associated with transgressions constitutes a decisive reason to conform, independently of what others do. In fact, in the traditional rational choice perspective, the only expectations that matter are those about the sanctions that follow compliance or non-compliance. In those frameworks, beliefs about how other people will act—as opposed to what they expect us to do—are not a relevant explanatory variable: however, this leads to predictions about norm compliance that often run counter to empirical evidence.

The traditional rational choice model of compliance depicts the individual as facing a decision problem in isolation: if there are sanctions for non-compliance, the individual will calculate the benefit of transgression against the cost of norm compliance, and eventually choose so as to maximize her expected utility. Individuals, however, seldom choose in isolation: they know the outcome of their choice will depend on the actions and beliefs of other individuals. Game theory provides a formal framework for modeling strategic interactions.

Thomas Schelling (1960), David Lewis (1969), Edna Ullmann-Margalit (1977), Robert Sugden (1986) and, more recently, Peyton Young (1993), Cristina Bicchieri (1993), and Peter Vanderschraaf (1995) have proposed a game-theoretic account according to which a norm is broadly defined as an equilibrium of a strategic interaction. In particular, a Nash equilibrium is a combination of strategies (one for each individual), such that each individual’s strategy is a best reply to the others’ strategies. Since it is an equilibrium, a norm is supported by self-fulfilling expectations in the sense that players’ beliefs are consistent, and thus the actions that follow from players’ beliefs will validate those very beliefs. Characterizing social norms as equilibria has the advantage of emphasizing the role that expectations play in upholding norms. On the other hand, this interpretation of social norms does not prima facie explain why people prefer to conform if they expect others to conform.

Take for example conventions such as putting the fork to the left of the plate, adopting a dress code, or using a particular sign language. In all these cases, my choice to follow a certain rule is conditional upon expecting most other people to follow it. Once my expectation is met, I have every reason to adopt the rule in question. In fact, if I do not use the sign language everybody else uses, I will not be able to communicate. It is in my immediate interest to follow the convention, since my main goal is to coordinate with other people. In the case of conventions, there is a continuity between the individual’s self-interest and the interests of the community that supports the convention. This is the reason why David Lewis models conventions as equilibria of coordination games . Such games have multiple equilibria, but once one of them has been established, players will have every incentive to keep playing it (as any deviation will be costly).

Take instead a norm of cooperation. In this case, the expectation that almost everyone abides by it may not be sufficient to induce compliance. If everyone is expected to cooperate one may be tempted, if unmonitored, to behave in the opposite way. The point is that conforming to social norms , as opposed to conventions, is almost never in the immediate interest of the individual. Often there is a discontinuity between the individual’s self-interest and the interests of the community that supports the social norm.

The typical game in which following a norm would provide a better solution (than the one attained by self-centered agents) is a mixed-motive game such as the prisoner’s dilemma or the trust game. In such games the unique Nash equilibrium represents a suboptimal outcome. It should be stressed that—whereas a convention is one among several equilibria of a coordination game—a social norm can never be an equilibrium of a mixed-motive game. However, Bicchieri (2006) has argued that when a norm exists it transforms the original mixed-motive game into a coordination one. As an example, consider the following prisoner’s dilemma game ( Figure 1 ), where the payoffs are B=Best, S=Second, T=Third, and W=Worst. Clearly the only Nash equilibrium is to defect (D), in which case both players get (T,T), a suboptimal outcome. Suppose, however, that society has developed a norm of cooperation; that is, whenever a social dilemma occurs, it is commonly understood that the parties should privilege a cooperative attitude. Should, however, does not imply “will”, therefore the new game generated by the existence of the cooperative norm has two equilibria: either both players defect or both cooperate.

Note that, in the new coordination game (which was created by the existence of the cooperative norm), the payoffs are quite different from those of the original prisoner’s dilemma. Thus there are two equilibria: if both players follow the cooperative norm they will play an optimal equilibrium and get (B,B), whereas if they both choose to defect they will get the suboptimal outcome (S,S). Players’ payoffs in the new coordination game differ from the original payoffs because their preferences and beliefs will reflect the existence of the norm. More specifically, if a player knows that a cooperative norm exists and has the right kind of expectations, then she will have a preference to conform to the norm in a situation in which she can choose to cooperate or to defect. In the new game generated by the norm’s existence, choosing to defect when others cooperate is not a good choice anymore (T,W). To understand why, let us look more closely to the preferences and expectations that underlie the conditional choice to conform to a social norm.

Bicchieri (2006) defines the expectations that underlie norm compliance, as follows:

Note that universal compliance is not usually needed for a norm to exist. However, how much deviance is socially tolerable will depend on the norm in question. Group norms and well-entrenched social norms will typically be followed by almost all members of a group or population, whereas greater deviance is usually accepted when norms are new or they are not deemed to be socially important. Furthermore, as it is usually unclear how many people follow a norm, different individuals may have different beliefs about the size of the group of followers, and may also have different thresholds for what “sufficiently large” means. What matters to conformity is that an individual believes that her threshold has been reached or surpassed. For a critical assessment of the above definition of norm-driven preferences, see Hausman (2008).

Brennan et al. (2013) also argue that norms of all kinds share in an essential structure. Norms are clusters of normative attitudes in a group, combined with the knowledge that such a cluster of attitudes exists. On their account, “A normative principle P is a norm within a group G if and only if:

  • A significant proportion of the members of G have P -corresponding normative attitudes; and
  • A significant proportion of the members of G know that a significant proportion of the members of G have P -corresponding attitudes” (Brennan et al. 2013: 29)

On this account, a “ P -corresponding normative attitude” is understood to be a judgment, emotional state, expectation, or other properly first personal normative belief that supports the principle P (e.g., Alice thinking most people should P would count as a normative attitude). Condition (i) is meant to reflect genuine first personal normative commitments, attitudes or beliefs. Condition (ii) is meant to capture those cases where individuals know that a large part of their group also shares in those attitudes. Putting conditions (i) and (ii) together offers a picture that the authors argue allows for explanatory work to be done on a social-level normative concept while remaining grounded in individual-level attitudes.

Consider again the new coordination game of Figure 1 : for players to obey the norm, and thus choose C, it must be the case that each expects the other to follow it. In the original prisoner’s dilemma, empirical beliefs would not be sufficient to induce cooperative behavior. When a norm exists, however, players also believe that others believe they should obey the norm, and may even punish them if they do not. The combined force of empirical and normative expectations makes norm conformity a compelling choice, be it because punishment may follow or just because one recognizes the legitimacy of others’ expectations (Sugden 2000).

It is important to understand that conformity to a social norm is always conditional on the expectations of what the relevant other/s will do. We prefer to comply with the norm as we have certain expectations. To make this point clear, think of the player who is facing a typical one-shot prisoner’s dilemma with an unknown opponent. Suppose the player knows a norm of cooperation exists and is generally followed, but she is uncertain as to whether the opponent is a norm-follower. In this case the player is facing the following situation ( Figure 2 ).

With probability p , the opponent is a norm-following type, and with probability \(1 - p\) she is not. According to Bicchieri, conditional preferences imply that having a reason to be fair, reciprocate or cooperate in a given situation does not entail having any general motive or disposition to be fair, reciprocate or cooperate as such. Having conditional preferences means that one may follow a norm in the presence of the relevant expectations, but disregard it in its absence. Whether a norm is followed at a given time depends on the actual proportion of followers, on the expectations of conditional followers about such proportion, and on the combination of individual thresholds.

As an example, consider a community that abides by strict norms of honesty. A person who, upon entering the community, systematically violates these norms will certainly be met with hostility, if not utterly excluded from the group. But suppose that a large group of thieves makes its way into this community. In due time, people would cease to expect honesty on the part of others, and would find no reason to be honest themselves in a world overtaken by crime. In this case, probably norms of honesty would cease to exist, as the strength of a norm lies in its being followed by many of the members of the relevant group (which in turn reinforces people’s expectations of conformity).

What we have discussed is a “rational reconstruction” of what a social norm is. Such a reconstruction is meant to capture some essential features of norm-driven behavior; also, this analysis helps us distinguish social norms from other constructs such as conventions or personal norms. A limit of this account, however, is that it does not indicate how such equilibria are attained or, in other terms, how expectations become self-fulfilling.

While neoclassical economics and game theory traditionally conceived of institutions as exogenous constraints, research in political economy has generated new insights into the study of endogenous institutions . Specifically, endogenous norms have been shown to restrict the individual’s action set and drive preferences over action profiles (Bowles 1998; Ostrom 2000). As a result, the “standard” economic framework positing exogenous (and in particular self-centered) preferences has come under scrutiny. Widely documented deviations from the predictions of models with self-centered agents have informed alternative accounts of individual choice (for one of the first models of “interdependent preferences”, see Stigler & Becker 1977).

Some alternative accounts have helped reconcile insights about norm-driven behavior with instrumental rationality (Elster 1989b). Moreover, they have contributed to informing the design of laboratory experiments on non-standard preferences (for a survey of early experiments, see Ledyard 1995; more recent experiments are reviewed by Fehr & Schmidt 2006 and Kagel & Roth 2016). In turn, experimental findings have inspired the formulation of a wide range of models aiming to rationalize the behavior observed in the lab (Camerer 2003; Dhami 2016).

It has been argued that the upholding of social norms could simply be modeled as the optimization of a utility function that includes the others’ welfare as an argument. For instance, consider some of the early “social preference” theories, such as Bolton and Ockenfels’ (2000) or Fehr and Schmidt’s (1999) models of inequity aversion. These frameworks can explain a good wealth of evidence on preferences for equitable income distributions; they cannot however account for conditional preferences like those reflecting principles of reciprocity (e.g., I will keep the common bathroom clean, if I believe my roommates do the same). As noted above, the approach to social norms taken by philosophically-inclined scholars has emphasized the importance of conditional preferences in supporting social norms. In this connection, we note that some of the social preference theories do account for motivations conditional on empirical beliefs, whereby a player upholds a principle of “fair” behavior if she believes her co-players will uphold it too (Rabin 1993; Dufwenberg & Kirchsteiger 2004; Falk & Fischbacher 2006; Charness & Rabin 2002). These theories presuppose that players are hardwired with a notion of fair or kind behavior, as exogenously defined by the theorist. Since they implicitly assume that all players have internalized a unique—exogenous—normative standpoint (as reflected in some notion of fairness or kindness), these theories do not explicitly model normative expectations. Hence, players’ preferences are assumed to be conditional solely on their empirical beliefs; that is, preferences are conditional on whether others will behave fairly (according to an exogenous principle) or not.

That said, we stress that social preferences should not be conflated with social norms. Social preferences capture stable dispositions toward an exogenously defined principle of conduct (Binmore 2010). By contrast, social norms are better studied as group-specific solutions to strategic problems (Sugden 1986; Bicchieri 1993; Young 1998b). Such solutions are brought about by a particular class of preferences (“norm-driven preferences”), conditional on the relevant set of empirical beliefs and normative expectations. In fact, we stress that “what constitutes fair or appropriate behavior” often varies with cultural or situational factors (Henrich et al. 2001; Cappelen et al. 2007; Ellingsen et al. 2012). Accounting for endogenous expectations is therefore key to a full understanding of social norms.

Relatedly, Guala (2016) offers a game-theoretic account of institutions, arguing that institutions are sets of rules in equilibrium. Guala’s view incorporates insights from two competing accounts of institutions: institutions-as-rules (perhaps best rendered by North 1990), and institutions-as-equilibria. From the first account, he captures the idea that institutions create rules that help to guide our behaviors and reduce uncertainty. With rules in place, we more or less know what to do, even in new situations. From the second, he captures the idea that institutions are solutions to coordination problems that arise from our normal interactions. The institutions give us reasons to follow them. The function of the rules, then, is to point to actions that promote coordination and cooperation. Because of the equilibrium nature of the rules, each individual has an incentive to choose those actions, provided others do too. Guala relies on a correlated equilibrium concept to unite the rules and equilibria accounts. On this picture, an institution is simply a correlated equilibrium in a game, where other correlated equilibria would have been possible.

Thrasher (2018) offers a comparative-functional analysis of norms that broadly aligns with the Bicchieri (2006) framework to help understand the durability of “bad norms.” Abbink et al. (2017) use public goods-like experiments to show how peer punishment can hold inefficient norms in place. This general framework can be helpful to understand why duels and honor killings can become stable (e.g. Thrasher and Handfield 2018, Handfield and Thrasher 2019). This work explores the signaling function of socially costly norms.

An alternative class of models explains norm compliance in terms of social image or self-image concerns (e.g., Andreoni and Bernheim 2009; Bénabou and Tirole 2006, 2011). These models assume that one tries to signal (to others or to one’s future self) that one has good “personal traits”, with such type-specific traits being imperfectly observed. More precisely, Bénabou and Tirole (2006) model the individual’s utility from contributing to a public good as a function of (i) material payoffs, (ii) intrinsic rewards from behaving altruistically, and (iii) reputational returns; in particular, the authors assume that reputational returns depend on the observers’ posterior expectations of the individual’s type. Bénabou and Tirole then consider (a refinement of) signaling equilibria, thereby allowing for multiple solutions to occur as a result of the interplay of individual motivations and of the level of observability of the actions. While models with reputational concerns do not explicitly define normative expectations, they generally posit that players care about their reputation under the assumption that acting altruistically is good or appropriate. Looking ahead, there is still work to do to fully formalize the interplay of (endogenous) normative expectations and empirical beliefs within a general model that is applicable to any game setting. Such a model should probably build on the “psychological game theory” framework (for discussion, see Battigalli and Dufwenberg 2022, p. 857; see also Bicchieri and Sontuoso 2015).

In what follows we focus on lab experiments that identify social norms by explicitly measuring both empirical and normative expectations.

Xiao and Bicchieri (2010) designed an experiment to investigate the impact on trust games of two potentially applicable—but conflicting—principles of conduct, namely, equality and reciprocity . Note that the former can be broadly defined as a rule that recommends minimizing payoff differences, whereas the latter recommends taking a similar action as others (regardless of payoff considerations). The experimental design involved two trust game variants: in the first one, players started with equal endowments; in the second one, the investor was endowed with twice the money that the trustee was given. In both cases, the investor could choose to transfer a preset amount of money to the trustee or keep it all. Upon receiving the money, the trustee could in turn keep it or else transfer back some of it to the investor: in the equal endowment condition (“baseline treatment”), both equality and reciprocity dictate that the trustee transfer some money back to the investor; by contrast, in the unequal endowment condition (“asymmetry treatment”), equality and reciprocity dictate different actions as the trustee could guarantee payoff equality only by making a zero back-transfer. Xiao and Bicchieri elicited subjects’ first- and second-order empirical beliefs (“how much do you think other participants in your role will transfer to their counterpart?”; “what does your counterpart think you will do?”) and normative expectations (“how much do you think your counterpart believes you should transfer to her?”). The experimental results show that a majority of trustees returned a positive amount whenever reciprocity would reduce payoff inequality (in the baseline treatment); by contrast, a majority of trustees did not reciprocate the investors’ transfer when doing so would increase payoff inequality (in the asymmetry treatment). Moreover, investors correctly believed that less money would be returned in the asymmetry treatment than in the baseline treatment, and most trustees correctly estimated investors’ beliefs in both treatments. However, in the asymmetry treatment empirical beliefs and normative expectations conflicted: this highlights that, when there is ambiguity as to which principle of conduct is in place, each subject will support the rule of behavior that favors her most.

Reuben and Riedl (2013) examine the enforcement of norms of contribution to public goods in homogeneous and heterogeneous groups, such as groups whose members vary in their endowment, contribution capacity, or marginal benefits. In particular, Reuben and Riedl are interested in the normative appeal of two potentially applicable rules: the efficiency rule (prescribing maximal contributions by all) and the class of relative contribution rules (prescribing a contribution that is “fair” relative to the contributions of others; e.g., equality and equity rules). Reuben and Riedl’s results show that, in the absence of punishment, no positive contribution norm emerged and all groups converged toward free-riding. By contrast, with punishment, contributions were consistent with the prescriptions of the efficiency rule in a significant subset of groups (irrespective of the type of group heterogeneity); in other groups, contributions were consistent with relative contribution rules. These results suggest that even in heterogeneous groups individuals can successfully enforce a contribution norm. Most notably, survey data involving third parties confirmed well-defined yet conflicting normative views about the aforementioned contribution rules; in other words, both efficiency and relative contribution rules are normatively appealing, and are indeed potential candidates for emerging contribution norms in different groups.

Bicchieri and Chavez (2010) designed an experiment to investigate norm compliance in ultimatum games. Specifically, their experiment involved a variant of the ultimatum game whereby the proposer could choose one of the following three options: ($5, $5) , ($8, $2) , or Coin (in which case one of the other two allocations would be selected at random). This design allows for two plausible notions of fairness: as an equal outcome ($5, $5) or as a fair procedure (Coin). The experimenters elicited subjects’ normative expectations about the actions they thought would be considered fair by most participants: proposers and responders showed a remarkable degree of agreement in their notions of fairness, as most subjects believed that a majority of participants deemed both ($5, $5) and Coin to be appropriate. Further, the experimenters had subjects play three instances of the above ultimatum game under different information conditions. In the “full information” condition, all participants knew that the Coin option was available, and that responders would know if their respective proposer had chosen Coin. In the “private information” condition, responders did not know that Coin was available to proposers, and proposers were aware of responders’ ignorance. In the “limited information” condition, participants knew that the Coin option was available, but responders would not be able to distinguish whether their respective proposer had implemented one of the two allocations directly or had chosen Coin instead. The experimental results show that when normative expectations supporting the Coin option were either absent (in the private condition) or could be defied without consequence (in the limited condition), the frequency of choice of ($5, $5) and ($8, $2), respectively, were considerably higher than those of Coin. Moreover, the frequency of Coin choices was highest in the public information condition, where such option was common knowledge and its outcome transparent: this shows that there proposers followed the rule of behavior that favored them most, and that such a rule was effectively a social norm. On the other hand, substantial norm evasion characterized proposers’ behavior in the limited information condition, where ($8, $2) was the most frequent choice.

In a subsequent study, Chavez and Bicchieri (2013) measured empirical and normative expectations (as well as behavior) of third parties who were given the opportunity to add to or deduct from the payoffs of subjects who had participated in an ultimatum game. Third parties tended to reward subjects involved in equal allocations and to compensate victims of unfair allocations (rather than punish unfair behavior); on the other hand, third parties were willing to punish when compensation was not an available option. The experimental results further show that third parties shared a notion of fairness (as indicated by their normative expectations), and that such notion was sensitive to contextual differences.

Krupka and Weber (2013) introduced an interesting procedure for identifying social norms by means of pre-play coordination games. In brief, using alternative (between-subjects) variants of the dictator game, Krupka and Weber had participants assess the extent to which different actions were collectively perceived as socially appropriate: subjects providing these ratings effectively faced a coordination game, as they were incentivized to match the modal response given by others in the same situation (such a pre-play coordination game was intended to verify the presence of shared normative expectations). Krupka and Weber went on to use these elicited assessments to predict other subjects’ compliance with the relevant social norm in each dictator game variant (for another application of the same elicitation procedure, see Gächter et al. 2013).

Similarly, Schram and Charness’ (2015) proposed a procedure for inducing a shared understanding of the relevant rule of behavior, in the lab. In short, Schram and Charness had participants in dictator games receive advice from a group of third parties. The information received simply revealed what a group of uninvolved subjects thought dictators ought to do : as such, the information received generated an exogenous variation in the dictators’ normative expectations. Schram and Charness’ results show that choices are indeed affected by this information.

Bicchieri and Xiao (2009) designed an experiment to investigate what happens when empirical and normative expectations conflict. To that end, participants in a dictator game were exposed to different pieces of information. Specifically, two groups of dictators were given some “descriptive information”; that is, they were told what other subjects had done in another session (i.e., one group was told that previous participants had made for the most part a generous offer, while the other group was told that most participants had made a selfish offer). Further, another two groups of dictators were given some “normative information”; that is, they were told what previous subjects said ought to be done (i.e., one group was told that most previous participants thought that one should make a generous offer, while the other group was told that most participants thought that one should make a selfish offer). Other groups were given both descriptive and normative information. The experimental results show that—whenever such information did not conflict—both descriptive and normative messages had a significant influence on dictators’ own expectations and subsequent choices. When messages conflicted in that one indicated generosity and the other indicated selfishness, only the descriptive information affected dictators’ behavior. This suggests that if people recognize that others are breaching the norm, then they will no longer feel compelled to follow the relevant rule of behavior themselves.

To conclude, the studies surveyed here provide evidence of the role played by expectations in affecting behavior in a variety of social dilemmas. In this regard, we note that in contrast to the vast literature on empirical beliefs, the number of lab studies that directly measure normative expectations is relatively limited: more research is clearly needed to investigate the interplay of empirical and normative information about applicable rules of behavior.

Thus far we have examined accounts of social norms that take for granted that a particular norm exists in a population. However, for a full account of social norms, we must answer two questions related to the dynamics of norms. First, we must ask how a norm can emerge. Norms require a set of corresponding beliefs and expectations to support them, and so there must be an account of how these arise. Second, we must investigate the conditions under which a norm is stable under some competitive pressure from other norms. Sometimes, multiple candidate norms vie for dominance in a population. Even if one norm has come to dominate the population, new norms can try to “invade” the existing norm’s population of adherents.

Let us now turn to the question of norm emergence. Here we can see three classes of models: first, a purely biological approach, second, a more cognitive approach, and third, a structured interactions approach. The most famous of the biological approaches to norms seek to explain cooperative behavior. The simplest models are kin selection models (Hamilton 1964). These models seek to explain altruistic tendencies in animals by claiming that, as selection acts on genes, those genes have an incentive to promote the reproductive success of other identical sets of genes found in other animals. This mode of explanation can provide an account of why we see cooperative behaviors within families, but being gene-centered, cannot explain cooperative behavior toward strangers (as strangers should not be sufficiently genetically related to merit altruistic behavior).

Models of “reciprocal altruism” (Trivers 1971, 1985), on the other hand, tell us that cooperative behavior has no chance of evolving in random pairings, but will evolve in a social framework in which individuals can benefit from building reputations for being nice guys. Reciprocal altruism, however, does not require an evolutionary argument; a simple model of learning in ongoing close-knit groups will do, and has the further advantage of explaining why certain types of cooperative behavior are more likely to emerge than others. All that matters in these models is that agents can properly identify other agents, such that they can maintain a record of their past behavior. This allows for the possibility of reputations: people who have the reputation of being cooperative will be treated cooperatively, and those who have a reputation of being unfair will be treated unfairly.

A variation on the idea of reciprocal altruism can be seen in Axelrod (1986). Axelrod presents a “norms game” in which agents probabilistically choose to comply with the norm, or deviate from it, and then other agents can probabilistically choose to punish any deviations at some cost to them. Agents can choose over time to be more or less “bold”, which determines the rate at which they attempt defections, and they can likewise choose to be more or less “vengeful”, which determines how often they punish. Axelrod noted that if the game is left like this, we find that the stable state is constant defection and no punishment. However, if we introduce a meta-norm—one that punishes people who fail to punish defectors—then we arrive at a stable norm in which there is no boldness, but very high levels of vengefulness. It is under these conditions that we find a norm emerge and remain stable. Axelrod’s model aims to illustrate that norms require meta-norms. That is, failure to retaliate against a defection must be seen as equivalent to a defection itself. What Axelrod does not analyze is whether there is some cost to being vigilant. Namely, watching both defectors and non-punishers may have a cost that, though nominal, might encourage some to abandon vigilance once there has been no punishment for some time.

Bicchieri, Duffy and Tolle (2004) present an alternative model of norm emergence to explain how a norm of impersonal trust/reciprocity can emerge and survive in a heterogeneous population. This model does not rely on a meta-norm of punishment; instead, it is purely driven by repeated interactions of conditional strategies. In their model, agents play anywhere from 1 to 30 rounds of a trust game for 1,000 iterations, relying on the 4 unconditional strategies, and the 16 conditional strategies that are standard for the trust game. After each round, agents update their strategies based on the replicator dynamic. As the number of rounds grows, a norm of impersonal trust/reciprocity emerges in the population. Most interestingly, however, the norm is not associated with a single strategy, but it is supported by several strategies behaving in similar ways. This model suggests that Trivers’ basic model works well in normal social contexts, but we can further enrich the story by allowing a social norm to supervene on several behavioral strategies.

Muldoon et al. (2012) explore a simpler approach to norm emergence that relies on individual reasoners weighing their individual interests against their social sensitivity. This is done across a number of model variants based on a simple standing ovation. A striking finding of their “symmetric” model is that norm emergence is fairly rare, but can also be distinguished from merely common behaviors. A more cognitively demanding approach was taken by Muldoon, Lisciandra and Hartmann (2012), in which bayesian reasoners can learn to “discover” norms that were not present, and have no particular value. This can happen when agents think there might be a social rule, and then over-interpret social evidence. These models combine to suggest that we should expect many arbitrary norms, rather than a functionalist argument for the presence of norms.

The third prominent model of norm emergence comes from Brian Skyrms (1996, 2004) and Jason Alexander (2007). In this approach, two different features are emphasized: relatively simple cognitive processes and structured interactions. Both have explored a variety of games (such as the prisoner’s dilemma, the stag hunt, divide the dollar, and the ultimatum game) as exemplars of situations that offer the possibility of the emergence of a moral norm. Though Skyrms occasionally uses the replicator dynamic, both tend to emphasize simpler mechanisms in an agent-based learning context. In particular, learning rules like “imitate the best” or best response are used, as they are much less cognitively demanding. Alexander justifies the use of these simpler rules on the grounds that, rather than fully rational agents, we are cognitively limited beings who rely on fairly simple heuristics for our decision-making. Rules like imitation are extremely simple to follow. Best response requires a bit more cognitive sophistication, but is still simpler than a fully Bayesian model with unlimited memory and computational power. These simpler learning rules provide the same function as the replicator dynamic: in between rounds of play, agents rely on their learning rule to decide what strategy to employ. Note that both Skyrms and Alexander tend to treat norms as single strategies.

The largest contribution of this strain of modeling comes not from the assumption of boundedly rational agents, but rather the careful investigation of the effects of particular social structures on the equilibrium outcomes of various games. Much of the previous literature on evolutionary games has focused on the assumptions of infinite populations of agents playing games against randomly-assigned partners. Skyrms and Alexander both rightly emphasize the importance of structured interaction. As it is difficult to uncover and represent real-world network structures, both tend to rely on examining different classes of networks that have different properties, and from there investigate the robustness of particular norms against these alternative network structures. Alexander (2007) in particular has done a very careful study of the different classical network structures, where he examines lattices, small world networks, bounded degree networks, and dynamic networks for each game and learning rule he considers. A final feature of Skyrms and Alexander’s work is a refinement on this structural approach: they separate out two different kinds of networks. First, there is the interaction network, which represents the set of agents that any given agent can actively play a game with. Second is the update network , which is the set of agents that an agent can “see” when applying her learning rule. The interaction network is thus one’s immediate community, whereas the update network is all that the agent can see. To see why this is useful, we can imagine a case not too different from how we live, in which there is a fairly limited set of other people we may interact with, but thanks to a plethora of media options, we can see much more widely how others might act. This kind of situation can only be represented by clearly separating the two networks.

Thus, what makes the theory of norm emergence of Skyrms and Alexander so interesting is its enriching the set of idealizations that one must make in building a model. The addition of structured interaction and structured updates to a model of norm emergence can help make clear how certain kinds of norms tend to emerge in certain kinds of situation and not others, which is difficult or impossible to capture in random interaction models.

Now that we have examined norm emergence, we must examine what happens when a population is exposed to more than one social norm. In this instance, social norms must compete with each other for adherents. This lends itself to investigations about the competitive dynamics of norms over long time horizons. In particular, we can investigate the features of norms and of their environments, such as the populations themselves, which help facilitate one norm becoming dominant over others, or becoming prone to elimination by its competitors. An evolutionary model provides a description of the conditions under which social norms may spread. One may think of several environments to start with. A population can be represented as entirely homogeneous, in the sense that everybody is adopting the same type of behavior, or heterogeneous to various degrees. In the former case, it is important to know whether the commonly adopted behavior is stable against mutations. The relevant concept here is that of an evolutionarily stable strategy (ESS; Maynard Smith & Price 1973; Taylor & Jonker 1978): when a population of individuals adopts such a strategy, it cannot be successfully invaded by isolated mutants, since the mutants will be at a disadvantage with respect to reproductive success. An evolutionarily stable strategy is a refinement of the Nash equilibrium in game theory. Unlike standard Nash equilibria, evolutionarily stable strategies must either be strict equilibria , or have an advantage when playing against mutant strategies. Since strict equilibria are always superior to any unilateral deviations, and the second condition requires that the ESS have an advantage in playing against mutants, the strategy will remain resistant to any mutant invasion. This is a difficult criterion to meet, however. For example, a classic Tit-For-Tat strategy in the prisoner’s dilemma is not an ESS. Many strategies perform equally well against it, including the very simple “Always Cooperate” strategy, let alone Tit-For-Two-Tats, and any number of variations. Tit-For-Tat is merely an evolutionarily neutral strategy relative to these others. If we only consider strategies that are defection-oriented, then Tit-For-Tat is an ESS, since it will do better against itself, and no worse than defection strategies when paired with them.

A more interesting case, and one relevant to a study of the reproduction of norms of cooperation, is that of a population in which several competing strategies are present at any given time. What we want to know is whether the strategy frequencies that exist at a time are stable, or if there is a tendency for one strategy to become dominant over time. If we continue to rely on the ESS solution concept, we see a classic example in the hawk-dove game. If we assume that there is no uncorrelated asymmetry between the players, then the mixed Nash equilibrium is the ESS. If we further assume that there is no structure to how agents interact with each other, this can be interpreted in two ways: either each player randomizes her strategy in each round of play, or we have a stable polymorphism in the population, in which the proportion of each strategy in the population corresponds to the frequency with which each strategy would be played in a randomizing approach. So, in those cases where we can assume that players randomly encounter each other, whenever there is a mixed solution ESS we can expect to find polymorphic populations.

If we wish to avoid the interpretive challenge of a mixed solution ESS, there is an alternative analytic solution concept that we can employ: the evolutionarily stable state. An evolutionarily stable state is a distribution of (one or more) strategies that is robust against perturbations, whether they are exogenous shocks or mutant invasions, provided the perturbations are not overly large. Evolutionarily stable states are solutions to a replicator dynamic. Since evolutionarily stable states are naturally able to describe polymorphic or monomorphic populations, there is no difficulty with introducing population-oriented interpretations of mixed strategies. This is particularly important when random matching does not occur, as under those conditions, the mixed strategy can no longer be thought of as a description of population polymorphism.

Now that we have seen the prominent approaches to both norm emergence and norm stability, we can turn to some general interpretive considerations of evolutionary models. An evolutionary approach is based on the principle that strategies with higher current payoffs will be retained, while strategies that lead to failure will be abandoned. The success of a strategy is measured by its relative frequency in the population at any given time. This is most easily seen in a game theoretic framework. A game is repeated a finite number of times with randomly selected opponents. After each round of the game, the actual payoffs and strategies of the players become public knowledge; on the basis of this information, each player adjusts her strategy for the next round. The payoff to an individual player depends on her choice as well as on the choices of the other players in the game, and players are rational in the sense that they are payoff-maximizers. In an evolutionary model, however, players learn and adapt in a non-Bayesian way, that is, they do not condition on past experience using Bayes’ Rule. In this sense, they are not typical rational learners (Nachbar 1990; Binmore & Samuelson 1992).

In an evolutionary approach behavior is adaptive, so that a strategy that did work well in the past is retained, and one that fared poorly will be changed. This can be interpreted in two ways: either the evolution of strategies is the consequence of adaptation by individual agents, or the evolution of strategies is understood as the differential reproduction of agents based on their success rates in their interactions. The former interpretation assumes short timescales for interactions: many iterations of the game over time thus represent no more than a few decades in time in total. The latter interpretation assumes rather longer timescales: each instance of strategy adjustment represents a new generation of agents coming into the population, with the old generation dying simultaneously. Let us consider the ramifications of each interpretation in turn.

In the first interpretation, we have agents who employ learning rules that are less than fully rational, as defined by what a Bayesian agent would have, both in terms of computational ability and memory. As such, these rules tend to be classified as adaptive strategies: they are reacting to a more limited set of data, with lower cognitive resources than what a fully rational learner would possess. However, there are many different adaptive mechanisms we may attribute to the players. One realistic adaptive mechanism is learning by trial and error; another plausible mechanism is imitation: those who do best are observed by others who subsequently emulate their behavior (Hardin 1982). Reinforcement learning is another class of adaptive behavior, in which agents tweak their probabilities of choosing one strategy over another based on the payoffs they just received.

In the second interpretation, agents themselves do not learn, but rather the strategies grow or shrink in the population according to the reproductive advantages that they bestow upon the agents that adhere to them. This interpretation requires very long timescales, as it requires many generations of agents before equilibrium is reached. The typical dynamics that are considered in such circumstances come from biology. A standard approach is something like the replicator dynamic. Norms grow or shrink in proportion to both how many agents adhere to them at a given time, and their relative payoffs. More successful strategies gain adherents at the expense of less-successful ones. This evolutionary process assumes a constant-sized (or infinite) population over time. This interpretation of an evolutionary dynamic, which requires long timescales, raises the question of whether norms themselves evolve slowly. Norms can rapidly collapse in a very short amount of time. This phenomenon could not be represented within a model whose interpretation is generational in nature. It remains an open question, however, as to whether such timescales can be appropriate for examining the emergence of certain kinds of norms. While it is known that many norms can quickly come into being, it is not clear if this is true of all norms.

Another challenge in using evolutionary models to study social norms is that there is a potential problem of representation. In evolutionary models, there is no rigorous way to represent innovation or novelty. Whether we look at an agent-based simulation approach, or a straightforward game-theoretic approach, the strategy set open to the players, as well as their payoffs, must be defined in advance. But many social norms rely on innovations, whether they are technological or social. Wearing mini-skirts was not an option until they were invented. Marxist attitudes were largely not possible until Marx. The age at which one gets married and how many children one has are highly linked to availability of and education about birth control technologies. While much of the study of norms has focused on more generic concepts such as fairness, trust, or cooperation, the full breadth of social norms covers many of these more specific norms that require some account of social innovation.

This representational challenge has broad implications. Even when we can analytically identify evolutionarily stable states in a particular game, which is suggestive of norms that will be converged upon, we now have a problem of claiming that this norm has prospects for long-term stability. Events like the publication of the Kinsey report can dramatically shift seemingly stable norms quite rapidly. As the underlying game changes in the representation, our previous results no longer apply. In the face of this representational problem, we can either attempt to develop some metric of the robustness of a given norm in the space of similar games, or more carefully scope the claims that we can make about the social norms that we study with this methodology.

Although some questions of interpretation and challenges of representation exist, an important advantage of the evolutionary approach is that it does not require sophisticated strategic reasoning in circumstances, such as large-group interactions, in which it would be unrealistic to assume it. People are very unlikely to engage in full Bayesian calculations in making decisions about norm adherence. Agents often rely on cognitive shortcuts to determine when norms ought to be in effect given a certain context, and whether or not they should adhere to them. Evolutionary models that employ adaptive learning strategies capture these kinds of cognitive constraints, and allow the theorist to explore how these constraints influence the emergence and stability of norms.

The study of social norms can help us understand a wide variety of seemingly puzzling behaviors. According to some accounts, a social norm results from conditional preferences for conforming to a relevant behavioral rule. Such preferences are conditional on two different kinds of beliefs: empirical and normative expectations.

This and other accounts of social norms still leave much to be investigated. Explaining how normative expectations come to exist remains an open question. Another open question to consider is how one could intervene to change socially harmful norms. While there have been initial investigations into these questions (Bicchieri 2016, Muldoon 2018a, 2018b), there is much more work to be done. One frontier in this area is in deploying behavioral tools such as nudging for fostering norm changes (Bicchieri 2022, 2023).

Finally, we stress that different contextual factors (such as the framing and characteristics of the strategic problem, the role one is assigned, the social category with which one identifies, as well as historical and chance events) often come to be associated with different notions of “appropriate behavior”. Accounting for endogenous expectations is therefore key to a full understanding of norm-driven behavior. More research—both theoretical and experimental—is needed to further illuminate the impact of expectations on strategic decisions.

  • Abbink, K., Gangadharan, L., Handfield, T., et al., 2017, Peer punishment promotes enforcement of bad social norms. Nat Commun 8(609). doi:10.1038/s41467-017-00731-0
  • Akerlof, George A., 1976, “The Economics of Caste and of the Rat Race and Other Woeful Tales”, Quarterly Journal of Economics , 90(4): 599–617. doi:10.2307/1885324
  • Alexander, Jason McKenzie, 2000, “Evolutionary Explanations of Distributive Justice”, Philosophy of Science , 67(3): 490–516. doi:10.1086/392792
  • –––, 2005, “The Evolutionary Foundations of Human Altruism”, Analyse & Kritik , 27(1): 106–113. [ Alexander 2005 available online ]
  • –––, 2007, The Structural Evolution of Morality , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511550997
  • Andreoni, James and B. Douglas Bernheim, 2009, “Social Image and The 50–50 Norm: A Theoretical and Experimental Analysis of Audience Effects”, Econometrica , 77(5): 1607–1636. doi:10.3982/ECTA7384
  • Arrow, Kenneth J., 1971, “A Utilitarian Approach to the Concept of Equality in Public Expenditure”, Quarterly Journal of Economics , 85(3): 409–15. doi:10.2307/1885930
  • Axelrod, Robert, 1984, The Evolution of Cooperation , New York: Basic Books.
  • –––, 1986, “An Evolutionary Approach to Norms”, American Political Science Review , 80(4): 1095–1111. doi:10.1017/S0003055400185016
  • Battigalli, Pierpaolo & Dufwenberg, Martin, 2009, “Dynamic Psychological Games”, Journal of Economic Theory , 144(1): 1–35. doi:10.1016/j.jet.2008.01.004
  • –––, 2022, “Belief-Dependent Motivations and Psychological Game Theory”, Journal of Economic Literature , 60(3): 833–882. doi:10.1257/jel.20201378
  • Bénabou, Roland and Jean Tirole, 2006, “Incentives and Prosocial Behavior”, American Economic Review , 96(5): 1652–1678. doi:10.1257/aer.96.5.1652
  • –––, 2011, “Identity, Morals, and Taboos: Beliefs as Assets”, Quarterly Journal of Economics , 126(2): 805–855. doi:10.1093/qje/qjr002
  • Bicchieri, Cristina, 1990, “Norms of Cooperation”, Ethics , 100(4): 838–861. doi:10.1086/293237
  • –––, 1993, Rationality and Coordination , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Second Edition, 1996.
  • –––, 1997, “Learning to Cooperate”, in Cristina Bicchieri, Richard C. Jeffrey, and Brian Skyrms, The Dynamics of Norms , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2002, “Covenants Without Swords: Group Identity, Norms, and Communication in Social Dilemmas”, Rationality and Society , 14(2): 192–228. doi:10.1177/1043463102014002003
  • –––, 2006, The Grammar of Society: The Nature and Dynamics of Social Norms , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511616037
  • –––, 2016, Norms in the Wild: How to Diagnose, Measure, and Change Social Norms , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780190622046.001.0001
  • –––, 2022, “Norm Nudging: How to Measure What We Want to Implement” in Behavioral Science in the Wild (pp. 82–107). University of Toronto Press.
  • –––, 2023, “Norm nudging and twisting preferences”, Behavioural Public Policy , 1–10.
  • Bicchieri, Cristina and Alex Chavez, 2010, “Behaving as Expected: Public Information and Fairness Norms”, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making , 23(2): 161–178. doi:10.1002/bdm.648
  • Bicchieri, Cristina, John Duffy, and Gil Tolle, 2004, “Trust Among Strangers”, Philosophy of Science , 71(3): 286–319. doi:10.1086/381411
  • Bicchieri, Cristina and Yoshitaka Fukui, 1999, “The Great Illusion: Ignorance, Informational Cascades and the Persistence of Unpopular Norms”, Business Ethics Quarterly , 9(1): 127–155. doi:10.2307/3857639
  • Bicchieri, Cristina and Azi Lev-On, 2007, “Computer-Mediated Communication and Cooperation in Social Dilemmas: An Experimental Analysis”, Politics, Philosophy and Economics , 6(2): 139–168. doi:10.1177/1470594X07077267
  • Bicchieri, Cristina and Alessandro Sontuoso, 2015, “I Cannot Cheat on You After We Talk”, in The Prisoner’s Dilemma , Martin Peterson (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 101–114. doi:10.1017/CBO9781107360174.007
  • –––, 2020, “Game-Theoretic Accounts of Social Norms”, in M. Capra, R. Croson, T. Rosenblatt, and M. Rigdon (eds.), The Handbook of Experimental Game Theory , Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing. doi:10.4337/9781785363337.00017
  • Bicchieri, Cristina and Erte Xiao, 2009, “Do the Right Thing: But Only If Others Do So”, Journal of Behavioral Decision Making , 22(2): 191–208. doi:10.1002/bdm.621
  • Bicchieri, Cristina and Jiji Zhang, 2012, “An Embarrassment of Riches: Modeling Social Preferences in Ultimatum Games”, in Philosophy of Economics , ( Handbook of the Philosophy of Science , Volume 13), Uskali Mäki (ed.), Amsterdam: Elsevier.
  • Binmore, Ken, 2010, “Social Norms or Social Preferences?”, Mind & Society , 9(2): 139–157. doi:10.1007/s11299-010-0073-2
  • Binmore, Kenneth G. and Larry Samuelson, 1992, “Evolutionary Stability in Repeated Games Played by Finite Automata”, Journal of Economic Theory , 57(2): 278–305. doI:10.1016/0022-0531(92)90037-I
  • Bolton, Gary E. and Axel Ockenfels, 2000, “ERC: A Theory of Equity, Reciprocity, and Competition”, American Economic Review , 90(1): 166–193. doi:10.1257/aer.90.1.166
  • Bornstein, Gary and Meyrav Ben-Yossef, 1994, “Cooperation in Intergroup and Single-Group Social Dilemmas”, Journal of Experimental Social Psychology , 30(1): 52–67. doi:10.1006/jesp.1994.1003
  • Bowles, Samuel, 1998, “Endogenous Preferences: The Cultural Consequences of Markets and Other Economic Institutions”, Journal of Economic Literature , 36(1): 75–111.
  • Brennan, Geoffrey, Lina Eriksson, Robert E. Goodin, and Nicholas Southwood, 2013, Explaining Norms , New York: Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199654680.001.0001
  • Brewer, Marilynn B., 1979, “In-group Bias in the Minimal Intergroup Situation: A Cognitive-Motivational Analysis”, Psychological Bulletin , 86(2): 307–324. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.86.2.307
  • –––, 1991, “The Social Self: On Being the Same and Different at the Same Time”, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin , 17(5): 475–482. doi:10.1177/0146167291175001
  • Brewer, Marilynn B. and Sherry K. Schneider, 1990, “Social Identity and Social Dilemmas: A Double-Edged Sword”, in Dominic Abrams and Michael A. Hogg (eds.), Social Identity Theory: Constructive and Critical Advances , Wheatsheaf, NY: Harvester.
  • Camerer, Colin F., 2003, Behavioral Game Theory. Experiments in Strategic Interaction , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Cancian, Francesca M, 1975, What are Norms? A Study of Beliefs and Action in a Maya Community , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Cappelen, Alexander W., Astri Drange Hole, Erik Ø Sørensen and Bertil Tungodden, 2007, “The Pluralism of Fairness Ideals: An Experimental Approach”, American Economic Review , 97(3): 818–827. doi:10.1257/aer.97.3.818
  • Charness, Gary and Matthew Rabin, 2002, “Understanding Social Preferences with Simple Tests”, Quarterly Journal of Economics , 117(3): 817–869. doi:10.1162/003355302760193904
  • Chavez, Alex K. and Cristina Bicchieri, 2013, “Third-Party Sanctioning and Compensation Behavior: Findings from the Ultimatum Game”, Journal of Economic Psychology , 39: 268–277. doi:10.1016/j.joep.2013.09.004
  • Cialdini, Robert B. and Noah J. Goldstein, 2004, “Social Influence: Compliance and Conformity”, Annual Review of Psychology , 55: 591–621. doi:10.1146/annurev.psych.55.090902.142015
  • Cialdini, Robert B., Carl A. Kallgren, and Raymond R. Reno, 1991, “A Focus Theory of Normative Conduct”, in Advances in Experimental Social Psychology , volume 24, Mark P. Zanna (ed.), New York: Academic Press, pp. 201–234. doi:10.1016/S0065-2601(08)60330-5
  • Coleman, James S., 1990, Foundations of Social Theory , Cambridge, MA: Belknap.
  • Coleman, Jules L., 1989, “Afterword: Rational Choice Approach to Legal Rules”, Chicago-Kent Law Review , 65(1): 177–191. [ Jules Coleman 1989 available online ]
  • Dawes, Robyn M., 1972, Fundamentals of Attitude Measurement , New York: Wiley.
  • –––, 1980, “Social Dilemmas”, Annual Review of Psychology , 31: 169–193. doi:10.1146/annurev.ps.31.020180.001125
  • –––, 1991, “Social Dilemmas, Economic Self-Interest, and Evolutionary Theory”, in Donald R. Brown and J.E. Keith Smith (eds.), Recent Research in Psychology: Frontiers of Mathematical Psychology: Essays in Honor of Clyde Coombs , New York: Springer-Verlag. doi:10.1007/978-1-4612-3088-5_2
  • Deutscher, Irwin, 1973, “What”, in his What We Say/What We Do: Sentiments & Acts , Glenview, IL: Scott Foresman.
  • Dhami, Sanjit S., 2016, The Foundations of Behavioral Economic Analysis , New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Diamond, A.S., 1935, Primitive Law , London: Watts.
  • Dufwenberg, Martin and Georg Kirchsteiger, 2004, “A Theory of Sequential Reciprocity”, Games and Economic Behavior , 47(2): 268–298. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2003.06.003
  • Durkheim, Émile, 1895 [1982], Les Règles de la méthode sociologique , Paris. Translated as The Rules of Sociological Method , W. D. Hall (trans.), Glencoe, IL: The Free Press.
  • –––, 1950 [1957], Leçons de Sociologie: Physique des Moeurs et du Droit , Istanbul: Cituri Biraderlet Basimevi. Translated as Professional Ethics and Civic Morals , Cornelia Brookfield (trans.), Glencoe, IL: The Free Press.
  • Ellickson, Robert C., 1991, Order Without Law: How Neighbors Settle Disputes , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Ellingsen, Tore, Magnus Johannesson, Johanna Mollerstrom, and Sara Munkhammar, 2012, “Social Framing Effects: Preferences or Beliefs?”, Games and Economic Behavior , 76(1): 117–130. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2012.05.007
  • Elster, Jon, 1989a, The Cement of Society: A Study of Social Order , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511624995
  • –––, 1989b, “Social Norms and Economic Theory” Journal of Economic Perspectives , 3(4): 99–117. doi:10.1257/jep.3.4.99
  • Falk, Armin and Urs Fischbacher, 2006, “A Theory of Reciprocity”, Games and Economic Behavior , 54(2): 293–315. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2005.03.001
  • Fehr, Ernst and Klaus M. Schmidt, 1999, “A Theory of Fairness, Competition, and Cooperation”, Quarterly Journal of Economics , 114(3): 817–868. doi:10.1162/003355399556151
  • –––, 2006, “The Economics of Fairness, Reciprocity and Altruism—Experimental Evidence and New Theories”, in Serge-Christophe Kolm and Jean Mercier Ythier (eds.), Handbook of The Economics of Giving, Altruism and Reciprocity (Volume 1), Amsterdam: North-Holland/Elsevier, pp. 615–691. doi:10.1016/S1574-0714(06)01008-6
  • Fishbein, Martin E., 1967, “A Consideration of Beliefs and Their Role in Attitude Measurement”, in Readings in Attitude Theory and Measurement , Martin E. Fishbein (ed.), New York: Wiley.
  • Freeman, Linton C. and Türröz Ataöv, 1960, “Invalidity of Indirect and Direct Measures of Attitude Toward Cheating”, Journal of Personality , 28(4): 443–447. doi:10.1111/j.1467-6494.1960.tb01631.x
  • Gächter, Simon, Daniele Nosenzo, and Martin Sefton, 2013, “Peer Effects in Pro-Social Behavior: Social Norms or Social Preferences?”, Journal of The European Economic Association , 11(3): 548–573. doi:10.1111/jeea.12015
  • Gaertner, Samuel L. and John F. Dovidio, 1986, “The Aversive Form of Racism”, in John F. Dovidio and Samuel L. Gaertner (eds.), Prejudice, Discrimination, and Racism: Theory and Research , Orlando, FL: Academic Press, pp. 61–89.
  • Geanakoplos, John, David Pearce, and Ennio Stacchetti, 1989, “Psychological Games and Sequential Rationality”, Games and Economic Behavior , 1(1): 60–79. doi:10.1016/0899-8256(89)90005-5
  • Geertz, Clifford, 1973, “Thick Description: Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture”, in The Interpretation of Cultures: Selected Essays , New York: Basic Books, pp. 3–30.
  • Gintis, Herbert, 2000, Game Theory Evolving , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Granovetter, Mark, 1985, “Economic Action and Social Structure: the Problem of Embeddedness”, American Journal of Sociology , 91(3): 481–510. doi:10.1086/228311
  • Guala, Francesco, 2016, Understanding Institutions: The Science and Philosophy of Living Together , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Hamilton W.D., 1964, “The Genetical Evolution of Social Behaviour I and II”, Journal of Theoretical Biology , 7: 1–16 and 17–52. doi:10.1016/0022-5193(64)90038-4 and 10.1016/0022-5193(64)90039-6
  • Handfield, T., & Thrasher, J., 2019, “Two of a kind: Are norms of honor a species of morality?” Biol Philos , 34, 39. doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9693-z
  • Hardin, Russell, 1982, Collective Action , New York: Resources for the Future.
  • Harding, John, Harold Proshansky, Bernard Kutner, and Isidor Chein, 1954 [1969], “Prejudice and Ethnic Relations”, in Gardner Lindzey (ed.), Handbook of Social Psychology , volume 2, Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, pp. 1021–1061. Reprinted in Gardner Lindzey and Elliot Aronson (eds.), Handbook of Social Psychology , second edition, volume 5, Reading, MA: Addison Wesley, 1969, pp. 1–76.
  • Hausman, Daniel M., 2008, “Fairness and Social Norms” Philosophy of Science , 75(5): 850–860. doi:10.1086/594529
  • Hechter, Michael and Karl-Dieter Opp, 2001, Social Norms , New York: Russel Sage Foundation.
  • Henrich, Joseph and Robert Boyd, 2001, “Why People Punish Defectors: Weak Conformist Transmission Can Stabilize Costly Enforcement of Norms in Cooperative Dilemmas”, Journal of Theoretical Biology , 208(1): 79–89. doi:10.1006/jtbi.2000.2202
  • Henrich, Joseph, Robert Boyd, Samuel Bowles, Colin Camerer, Ernst Fehr, Herbert Gintis, and Richard McElreath, 2001, “In Search of Homo Economicus: Behavioral Experiments in 15 Small-Scale Societies”, American Economic Review , 91(2): 73–78. doi:10.1257/aer.91.2.73
  • Hirshmann, Albert O., 1982, Shifting Involvements: Private Interest and Public Action , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Hoebel, Adamson E., 1954, The Law of Primitive Man , Cambridge, MA: Atheneum.
  • Hogg, Michael A. and John C. Turner, 1987, “Social Identity and Conformity: A Theory of Referent Informational Influence”, in William Doise and Serge Moscovici (eds.), Current Issues in European Social Psychology , Volume 2, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 139–182.
  • Homans, George Caspar, 1950, The Human Group , New York: Harcourt, Brace & Company.
  • –––, 1961, Social Behavior , New York: Harcourt Brace and World.
  • Insko, Chester A. and John Schopler, 1967, “Triadic Consistency: A Statement of Affective-Cognitive-Conative Consistency”, Psychological Review , 74(5): 361–376. doi:10.1037/h0020278
  • Kagel, John H. and Alvin E. Roth, 2016, Handbook of Experimental Economics , Volume 2, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Klassen, Albert D., Colin J. Williams, and Eugene E. Levitt, 1989, Sex and Morality in the U.S.: An Empirical Enquiry Under the Auspices of the Kinsey Institute , Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press.
  • Kramer, Roderick M. and Marilynn B. Brewer, 1984, “Effects of Group Identity on Resource Use in a Simulated Commons Dilemma”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 46(5): 1044–1057. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.46.5.1044
  • Krupka, Erin L. and Roberto A. Weber, 2013, “Identifying Social Norms Using Coordination Games: Why Does Dictator Game Sharing Vary?”, Journal of The European Economic Association , 11(3): 495–524. doi:10.1111/jeea.12006
  • LaPiere, Richard T., 1934, “Attitudes vs. Actions”, Social Forces , 13(2): 230–237. doi:10.2307/2570339
  • Ledyard, John, 1995, “Public Goods Experiments”, in John H. Kagel and Alvin E. Roth (eds.), The Handbook of Experimental Economics , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
  • Lewis, David, 1969, Convention: A Philosophical Study , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. doi:10.1002/9780470693711
  • –––, 1975, “Languages and Language”, in Language, Mind, and Knowledge , ( Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science , 6), Keith Gunderson (ed.), Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 3–35. [ Lewis 1975 available online ]
  • López-Pérez, Raúl, 2008, “Aversion to Norm-Breaking: A Model”, Games and Economic Behavior , 64(1): 237–267. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2007.10.009
  • Mackay, Charles, 1841, Extraordinary Popular Delusions and the Madness of Crowds , N. Stone (ed.), Hertfordshire: Wordsworth, 1995.
  • Mackie, G., 1996, “Ending Footbinding and Infibulation: A Convention Account”, American Sociological Review , 61(6): 999–1017. doi:10.2307/2096305
  • Matza, David, 1964, Delinquency and Drift , New York: Wiley.
  • Maynard Smith, J. and G. R. Price, 1973, “The Logic of Animal Conflict”, Nature , 246(5427): 15–18. doi:10.1038/246015a0
  • Miller, Dale T. and Rebecca K. Ratner, 1996, “The Power of the Myth of Self-Interest”, in Leo Montada and Melvin J. Lerner (eds.), Current Societal Concerns About Justice , New York: Plenum Press. doi:10.1007/978-1-4757-9927-9_3
  • Muldoon, Ryan, 2017, “Perspectives, Norms and Agency”, Social Philosophy and Policy, 34(1): 260–276. doi:10.1017/S0265052517000127
  • –––, 2018a, “Understanding Norms and Changing Them”, Social Philosophy and Policy, 35(1): 128–148. doi:10.1017/S0265052518000092
  • –––, 2018b, “Norms, Nudges, and Autonomy”, In: Boonin, D. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophy and Public Policy . Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-93907-0_18
  • –––, 2020, “Social Norms and Social Order”, in: Chartier and Van Schoelandt (eds) The Routledge Handbook of Anarchy and Anarchist Thought . Routledge.
  • Muldoon, R., Lisciandra, C., Bicchieri, C., Hartmann, S., & Sprenger, J., 2014, “On the emergence of descriptive norms”, Politics, Philosophy & Economics , 13(1): 3–22. doi:10.1177/1470594X12447791
  • Muldoon, R., Lisciandra, C. & Hartmann, S., 2014, “Why are there descriptive norms? Because we looked for them”, Synthese 191, 4409–4429. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0534-y
  • Nachbar, J.H., 1990, “‘Evolutionary’ Selection Dynamics in Games: Convergence and Limit Properties”, International Journal of Game Theory , 19(1): 59–89. doi:10.1007/BF01753708
  • North, Douglass C., 1990, “A Transaction Cost Theory of Politics” Journal of Theoretical Politics , 2(4): 355–367. doi:10.1177/0951692890002004001
  • O’Gorman, Hubert J., 1975, “Pluralistic Ignorance and White Estimates of White Support for Racial Segregation”, Public Opinion Quarterly , 39(3): 313–330. doi:10.1086/268231
  • Olson, Mancur, 1965 [1971], The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups , revised edition, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Ostrom, Elinor, 2000, “Collective Action and The Evolution of Social Norms”, Journal of Economic Perspectives , 14(3): 137–158. doi:10.1257/jep.14.3.137
  • Pagel, Elaine, 2003, Beyond Belief: The Secret Gospel of Thomas , New York: Vintage Books.
  • Parsons, Talcott, 1951, The Social System , New York: Routledge.
  • –––, 1937 [1968], The Structure of Social Action. A Study in Social Theory with Special Reference to a Group of Recent European Writers , New York, London: Free Press.
  • Parsons, Talcott and Edward A. Shils, 1951, Towards a General Theory of Action , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Posner, Eric A., 2000, Law and Social Norms , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Prentice, Deborah A. and Dale T. Miller, 1993, “Pluralistic Ignorance and Alcohol Use on Campus: Some Consequences of Misperceiving the Social Norm”, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology , 64(2): 243–56. doi:10.1037/0022-3514.64.2.243
  • Rabin, Matthew, 1993, “Incorporating Fairness into Game Theory and Economics”, American Economic Review , 83(5): 1281–1302.
  • Reuben, Ernesto and Arno Riedl, 2013, “Enforcement of Contribution Norms in Public Good Games with Heterogeneous Populations”, Games and Economic Behavior , 77(1): 122–137. doi:10.1016/j.geb.2012.10.001
  • Robinson, Claude E., 1932, Straw Votes: A Study of Political Prediction , New York: Columbia University Press.
  • Rommetveit, Ragnar, 1955, Social Norms and Roles: Explorations in the Psychology of Enduring Social Pressures with Empirical Contributions from Inquiries into Religious Attitudes and Sex Roles of Adolescents from Some Districts in Western Norway , Oslo: Akedemisk Forlag.
  • Schelling, Thomas C., 1960, The Strategy of Conflict , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1978, Micromotives and Macrobehavior , New York: Norton.
  • Schram, Arthur and Gary Charness, 2015, “Inducing Social Norms in Laboratory Allocation Choices”, Management Science , 61(7): 1531–1546. doi:10.1287/mnsc.2014.2073
  • Scott, John Finley, 1971, Internalization of Norms: A Sociological Theory of Moral Commitment , Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
  • Sherif, Muzafer, 1936, The Psychology of Social Norms , New York: Harper.
  • Skyrms, Brian, 1996, Evolution of the Social Contract , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511806308
  • –––, 2004, The Stag Hunt and the Evolution of Social Structure , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139165228
  • Stigler, George J. and Gary S. Becker, 1977, “De Gustibus Non Est Disputandum”, American Economic Review , 67(2): 76–90.
  • Sugden, Robert, 1986 [2004], The Economics of Rights, Co-operation and Welfare , second edition, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2004.
  • –––, 2000, “The Motivating Power of Expectations”, in Julian Nida-Rümelin and Wolfgang Spohn (eds.), Practical Rationality, Rules, and Structure , Dordrecht: Kluwer. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-9616-9_7
  • Tajfel, Henri, 1973, “The Roots of Prejudice: Cognitive Aspects”, in Psychology and Race , Peter Watson (ed.), Chicago: Aldine.
  • –––, 1981, Human Groups and Social Categories: Studies in Social Psychology , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Taylor, Peter D. and Leo B. Jonker, 1978, “Evolutionary Stable Strategies and Game Dynamics”, Mathematical Biosciences , 40(1–2): 145–156. doi:10.1016/0025-5564(78)90077-9
  • Thibaut, John W. and Harold H. Kelley, 1959, The Social Psychology of Groups , New York: Wiley.
  • Thrasher, John, 2018, “Evaluating bad norms” Social Philosophy and Policy, 35(1): 196–216. doi:10.1017/S0265052518000055
  • Thrasher, J., & Handfield, T., 2018, “Honor and Violence”, Hum Nat 29, 371–389. doi:10.1007/s12110-018-9324-4
  • Trivers, Robert L., 1971, “The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism”, Quarterly Review of Biology , 46(1): 35–57. doi:10.1086/406755
  • –––, 1985, Social Evolution , Menlo Park, CA: Benjamin/Cummings.
  • Turnbull, C. M., 1972, The Mountain People , New York: Touchstone.
  • Turner, John C., Michael A. Hogg, Penelope J. Oakes, Stephen D. Reicher, and Margaret S. Wetherell, 1987, Rediscovering the Social Group: A Self-Categorization Theory , Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Ullmann-Margalit, Edna, 1977, The Emergence of Norms , Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  • Vanderschraaf, Peter, 1995, “Convention as Correlated Equilibrium”, Erkenntnis , 42(1): 65–87. doi:10.1007/BF01666812
  • Warner, Lyle G. and Melvin L. DeFleur, 1969, “Attitude as An Interactional Concept: Social Constraint and Social Distance as Intervening Variables Between Attitudes and Action”, American Sociological Review , 34(2): 153–169. doi:10.2307/2092174
  • Wicker, Allan W., 1969, “Attitude versus Actions: The Relationship of Verbal and Overt Behavioral Responses to Attitude Objects”, A Journal of Social Issues , 25(4): 41–78. doi:10.1111/j.1540-4560.1969.tb00619.x
  • Wrong, Dennis H., 1961, “The Oversocialized Conception of Man in Modern Sociology”, American Sociological Review , 26(2): 183–193. doi:10.2307/2089854
  • Wuthnow, Robert, 1991, Acts of Compassion: Caring for Others and Helping Ourselves , Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Xiao, Erte and Cristina Bicchieri, 2010, “When Equality Trumps Reciprocity”, Journal of Economic Psychology , 31(3): 456–470. doi:10.1016/j.joep.2010.02.001
  • Young, H. Peyton, 1993, “The Evolution of Conventions”, Econometrica , 61(1): 57–84. doi:10.2307/2951778
  • –––, 1998a, “Social Norms and Economic Welfare”, European Economic Review , 42(3–5): 821–830. doi:10.1016/S0014-2921(97)00138-4
  • –––, 1998b, Individual Strategy and Social Structure: An Evolutionary Theory of Institutions , Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.
  • Arló-Costa, Horacio and Arthur Paul Pedersen, “ Social Norms, Rational Choice and Belief Change ”, manuscript, Carnegie Mellon Research Showcase.
  • Axelrod, Robert, 1992, “ How to Promote Cooperation ”, Current Contents—Social and Behavioral Sciences , 44: 10 (November 2, 1992); this is a scan of the version that appeared in Current Contents—Arts and Humanities , 23: 16 (November 9, 1992).
  • Selected Papers on Social Norms at EconPapers .
  • Social Norm , entry in Wikipedia .

altruism | belief | common knowledge | convention | evolution | game theory | game theory: evolutionary | morality: and evolutionary biology | normative cognition, psychology of | social institutions

Acknowledgments

A portion of section 6 of this entry has been adapted from “Game-Theoretic Accounts of Social Norms”, by Cristina Bicchieri and Alessandro Sontuoso, in The Handbook of Experimental Game Theory , Mónica Capra, Rachel Croson, Tanya Rosenblatt, and Mary Rigdon (eds.), Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing, 2020.

Copyright © 2023 by Cristina Bicchieri < cb36 @ sas . upenn . edu > Ryan Muldoon < ryan . muldoon @ gmail . com > Alessandro Sontuoso < sontuoso @ sas . upenn . edu >

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

MIT Libraries home DSpace@MIT

  • DSpace@MIT Home
  • MIT Libraries
  • Doctoral Theses

Essays on social norms

Thumbnail

Other Contributors

Terms of use, description, date issued, collections.

helpful professor logo

102 Examples of Social Norms (List)

social norms examples and definition, explained below

Social norms are the unspoken rules that govern how people interact with each other. They can vary from culture to culture, and even from group to group within a culture.

Some social norms are so ingrained in our psyches that we don’t even think about them; we just automatically do what is expected of us. Social norms examples include covering your mouth when you cough, waiting your turn, and speaking softly in a library.

Breaking societal norms can sometimes lead to awkward or uncomfortable situations. For example, if you’re in a library where it’s considered rude to talk on your cell phone, and you answer a call, you’ll likely get some disapproving looks from the people around you.

Understanding the social norms of the place you’re visiting is an important part of cultural etiquette to show respect for the people around you.

Examples of Social Norms

  • Greeting people when you see them.
  • Saying “thank you” for favors.
  • Holding the door open for others.
  • Standing up when someone else enters the room.
  • Offering to help someone carrying something heavy.
  • Speaking quietly in public places.
  • Waiting in line politely.
  • Respecting other people’s personal space.
  • Disposing of trash properly.
  • Refraining from eating smelly foods in public.
  • Paying for goods or services with a smile.
  • Complimenting others on their appearance or achievements.
  • Asking others about their day or interests.
  • Avoiding gossip and rumors.
  • Volunteering to help others in need.
  • Saying “I’m sorry” when you’ve made a mistake.
  • Supporting others in their time of need.
  • Participating in group activities.
  • Respecting authority figures.
  • Being on time for important engagements.
  • Avoiding interrupting others when they are speaking.
  • Showing interest in other people’s lives and experiences.
  • Refraining from using offensive language or gestures.
  • Being honest and truthful with others at all times.
  • Treating others with kindness and respect, regardless of their social status or background.
  • Putting the needs of others before your own.
  • Participating in charitable works and activities.
  • Helping others whenever possible.
  • Welcoming guests into your home or place of business.
  • Nodding, smiling, and looking people in the eyes to show you are listening to them.
  • Following the laws and regulations of your country.
  • Respecting the rights and beliefs of others.
  • Cooperating with others in order to achieve common goals.
  • Being tolerant and understanding of different viewpoints.
  • Displaying good manners and etiquette in social interactions.
  • Waiting in line for your turn.
  • Taking your shoes off before walking into someone’s house.
  • Putting your dog on a leash in parks and other public spaces.
  • Letting the elderly or pregnant people take your seat on a bus.

Social Norms for Students

  • Arrive to class on time and prepared.
  • Pay attention and take notes.
  • Stay quiet when other students are working.
  • Raise your hand if you have a question.
  • Do your homework and turn it in on time.
  • Participate in class discussions.
  • Respect your teachers and classmates.
  • Follow the school’s rules and regulations.
  • Use appropriate language and behavior.
  • Ask permission to be excused if you need to go to the bathroom.
  • Go to the bathroom before class begins.
  • Keep your workspace clean.
  • Do not plagiarize or cheat.
  • Wait your turn to speak.
  • Ask permission to use other people’s supplies.
  • Include all your peers in your group when doing group work.

Related: Classroom Rules for Middle School

Social Norms while Dining Out

  • Wait to be seated.
  • Remain seated until everyone is served.
  • Don’t reach across the table.
  • Use your napkin.
  • Don’t chew with your mouth open.
  • Don’t talk with your mouth full.
  • Keep elbows off the table.
  • Use a fork and knife when eating.
  • Drink from a glass, not from the bottle or carton.
  • Request more bread or butter only if you’re going to eat it all.
  • Don’t criticize the food or service.
  • Thank your server when you’re finished.
  • Leave a tip if you’re satisfied with the service.

Social Norms while using your Phone

  • Keep your phone on silent or vibrate mode while in meetings.
  • Don’t answer your phone in a public place unless it’s an emergency.
  • Don’t talk on the phone while driving.
  • Don’t text while driving.
  • Don’t take or make calls during class.
  • Don’t use your phone in a movie theater.
  • Turn off your phone when you’re with someone else.
  • Place your phone on airplane mode while flying.
  • Do not look at someone else’s phone.
  • Ensure your ringtone is inoffensive when in public or around children.

Social Norms in Libraries

  • Be quiet and respect the other patrons.
  • Don’t talk on your phone.
  • Don’t bring food or drinks into the library.
  • Don’t sleep in the library.
  • Don’t bring pets into the library.
  • Return all books to the correct location.
  • Don’t mark or damage library books.
  • Make sure your cell phone is turned off.
  • Return your books on time.

Social Norms in Other Countries

  • In France, it is considered polite to kiss acquaintances on both cheeks when meeting them.
  • In Japan, it is customary to take your shoes off when entering someone’s home.
  • In India, it is considered rude to show the soles of your feet or to point your feet at someone else.
  • In Italy, it is common for people to give each other a light kiss on the cheek as a gesture of hello or goodbye.
  • In China, it is customary to leave some food on your plate after eating, as a sign of respect for the cook.
  • In Spain, it is customary to call elders “Don” or “Doña.”
  • In Iceland, it is considered polite to say “thank you” (Takk) after every meal.
  • In Thailand, it is customary to remove your shoes before entering a home or temple.
  • In Germany, it is customary to shake hands with everyone you meet, both men and women.
  • In Argentina, it is customary for people to hug and kiss cheeks as a gesture of hello or goodbye.

Social Norms that Should be Broken

  • “ Women should be polite” – Stand up for what you believe in, even if it makes you look bossy.
  • “Don’t draw attention to yourself” – Embrace your uniqueness and difference so long as you’re respectful of others.
  • “Don’t question your parents or your boss” – Protest bad behavior from people in authority if you know you’re morally right.
  • “Mistakes are embarrassing” – It’s okay to make mistakes and be seen to fail. It means you’re making an effort and pushing your boundaries.
  • “Respect your elders” – If your elders are engaging in bad behavior, stand up to them and let them know you’re taking note of what they’re doing.

Cultural vs Social Norms

Cultural norms are the customs and traditions that are passed down from one generation to the next. They’re connected to the traditions, values, and practices of a particular culture.

Societal norms, on the other hand, reflect the current social standard for appropriate behavior within a society. In modern multicultural societies, there are different groups with different cultural norms, but they must all agree on a common set of social norms for public spaces.

We also have a concept called group norms , which define how smaller groups – like workplace teams or sports teams – will operate. These might differ from group to group, and are highly dependant on the expectations and standards of the group/team leader.

Norms Change Depending on the Context

Norms are different depending on different contexts, including in different eras, and in different societies. What might be considered polite in one context could be considered rude in another.

For example, norms in the 1950s were much more gendered. Negative gender stereotypes restricted women because it was normative for women to be quiet, polite, and submissive in public. Today, women have much more equality.

Similarly, the norms and taboos in the United States will be very different from those in China. For example, Chinese businessmen are often expected to share expensive gifts during negotiations. In the United States, this could be considered bordering on bribery.

What are the Four Types of Norms?

There are four types of norms : folkways, mores, taboos, and laws.

  • Folkways are social conventions that are not strictly enforced, but are generally considered to be polite or appropriate. An example of a folkway is covering your mouth when you sneeze.
  • Mores are social conventions that are considered to have a moral dimension. Due to their moral dimension, they’re generally considered to be more important than folkways. Violation of mores can result in social sanctions so they often overlap with laws (mentioned below). An example of a more is not drinking and driving.
  • Taboos are considered ‘negative norms’, or things that you should avoid doing. If you do them, you’ll be seen as rude. An example of a taboo is using your phone in a movie theater or spitting indoors.
  • Laws are the most formal and serious type of norm. They are usually enforced by the government and can result in criminal penalties if violated. Examples of laws include not stealing from others and not assaulting others.

Conclusion: What are Social Norms?

Social norms are defined as the unspoken rules that help us to get along with others in a polite and respectful manner. It’s important to follow them so that we can maintain a positive social environment for everyone involved. Social norms examples include not spitting indoors, covering your mouth when you sneeze, and shaking hands with everyone you meet.

Chris

Chris Drew (PhD)

Dr. Chris Drew is the founder of the Helpful Professor. He holds a PhD in education and has published over 20 articles in scholarly journals. He is the former editor of the Journal of Learning Development in Higher Education. [Image Descriptor: Photo of Chris]

  • Chris Drew (PhD) https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/ 5 Top Tips for Succeeding at University
  • Chris Drew (PhD) https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/ 50 Durable Goods Examples
  • Chris Drew (PhD) https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/ 100 Consumer Goods Examples
  • Chris Drew (PhD) https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/ 30 Globalization Pros and Cons

Leave a Comment Cancel Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Thank you for visiting nature.com. You are using a browser version with limited support for CSS. To obtain the best experience, we recommend you use a more up to date browser (or turn off compatibility mode in Internet Explorer). In the meantime, to ensure continued support, we are displaying the site without styles and JavaScript.

  • View all journals
  • Explore content
  • About the journal
  • Publish with us
  • Sign up for alerts
  • News & Views
  • Published: 17 December 2018

SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY

Social norms and how they impact behaviour

  • Katherine J. Reynolds 1  

Nature Human Behaviour volume  3 ,  pages 14–15 ( 2019 ) Cite this article

1981 Accesses

13 Citations

14 Altmetric

Metrics details

  • Human behaviour

There is wide interest in the social norms construct across psychology, economics, law and social marketing. Now a study investigates an important missing piece in the social norms’ puzzle: what is the underlying process that explains how norms impact behaviour? The answer: self–other similarity (self-categorization) and internalization.

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution

Relevant articles

Open Access articles citing this article.

Co-evolution of conditional cooperation and social norm

  • Balaraju Battu

Scientific Reports Open Access 03 October 2023

Access options

Access Nature and 54 other Nature Portfolio journals

Get Nature+, our best-value online-access subscription

24,99 € / 30 days

cancel any time

Subscribe to this journal

Receive 12 digital issues and online access to articles

111,21 € per year

only 9,27 € per issue

Buy this article

  • Purchase on Springer Link
  • Instant access to full article PDF

Prices may be subject to local taxes which are calculated during checkout

Hallsworth, M. et al. Lancet 387 , 1743–1752 (2016).

Article   Google Scholar  

Nolan, J. M., Schultz, P. W., Cialdini, R. B., Goldstein, N. J. & Griskevicius, V. Pers. Soc. Psychol. Bull. 34 , 913–923 (2008).

Reynolds, K. J., Subasic, E. & Tindall, K. Soc. Pers. Psychol. Compass 9 , 45–56 (2015).

Cialdini, R. B. Pre-suasion: A Revolutionary Way to Influence and Persuade 1st edn (Simon & Schuster, New York, 2016).

Turner, J. C. & Reynolds, K. J. in Handbook of Theories in Social Psychology (eds Van Lange, P., Kruglanski, A. & Higgins, T.) 399–417 (Sage, Thousand Oaks, 2012).

Reynolds, K. J. & Branscombe, N. R. in The Psychology of Change: Life Contexts, Experiences, and Identities (eds Reynolds, K. J. & Branscombe, N. R.) 265–281 (Psychology Press, London, 2015).

Pryor, C., Perfors, A. & Howe, P. D. L. Nat. Hum. Behav . https://doi.org/s41562-018-0489-y (2018).

Turner, J. C. Eur. J. Soc. Psychol. 35 , 1–22 (2005).

Nyborg, K. et al. Science 354 , 42–43 (2016).

Article   CAS   Google Scholar  

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Research School of Psychology, The Australian National University, Canberra, Australian Capital Territory, Australia

Katherine J. Reynolds

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Katherine J. Reynolds .

Ethics declarations

Competing interests.

The author declares no competing interests.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article.

Reynolds, K.J. Social norms and how they impact behaviour. Nat Hum Behav 3 , 14–15 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-018-0498-x

Download citation

Published : 17 December 2018

Issue Date : January 2019

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1038/s41562-018-0498-x

Share this article

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

This article is cited by

Scientific Reports (2023)

Trust in science, social consensus and vaccine confidence

  • Patrick Sturgis
  • Ian Brunton-Smith
  • Jonathan Jackson

Nature Human Behaviour (2021)

Quick links

  • Explore articles by subject
  • Guide to authors
  • Editorial policies

Sign up for the Nature Briefing newsletter — what matters in science, free to your inbox daily.

social norms essay

Home — Essay Samples — Sociology — Social Norms — Norm Violation in Sociology

test_template

Norm Violation in Sociology

  • Categories: Deviance Social Norms

About this sample

close

Words: 1203 |

Published: Feb 12, 2024

Words: 1203 | Pages: 3 | 7 min read

Table of contents

Social norms essay: research methodology, breaking a social norm essay: research results, discussion: the consequences of social norm violation, norm violation faq.

  • What is norm violation in sociology? Norm violation in sociology refers to the intentional or unintentional breaking of social rules and norms that govern society.
  • How do social norms shape society? Social norms play a significant role in shaping society by determining acceptable behavior. They provide guidelines for how individuals should act and interact with others in their community.
  • Can social norms change over time? Yes, social norms are not fixed and can change over time. What was once considered typical or acceptable may now be deemed unacceptable or outdated.
  • What was the focus of the norm violation experiment described in the essay? The norm violation experiment aimed to observe and analyze how individuals would respond to the violation of the social norm of using gender-segregated public restrooms. The experiment sought to determine whether people would attempt to correct the behavior or ignore it, highlighting their readiness to address norm violations.
  • What were the results of the norm violation experiment? The most common reaction observed was subtle confusion without any subsequent comments. Men recognized that the woman had entered the wrong restroom but chose to either leave hurriedly or avoid entering after seeing her inside. This indicated a preference to either escape or ignore norm violations rather than confront them. Only a few individuals attempted to point out the mistake, while others simply asked her to leave. There were no signs of disrespect or physical contact, with only one instance of rude behavior.
  • What were the consequences of the norm violation for the experimenter? The experimenter initially felt uncertainty and shame regarding her behavior, but as the experiment progressed, she became more accustomed to the situation. This suggests that hedonic adaptation may occur in similar circumstances, leading to a normalization of the behavior.
  • What does the norm violation experiment suggest about society? The norm violation experiment suggests that people prioritize their personal space and time over addressing others' social behavior directly. This may reflect an increasing trend towards individualism and selfishness in society. However, it is important to recognize the importance of cooperation and adherence to social norms for the functioning and survival of society.

Image of Dr. Oliver Johnson

Cite this Essay

Let us write you an essay from scratch

  • 450+ experts on 30 subjects ready to help
  • Custom essay delivered in as few as 3 hours

Get high-quality help

author

Dr. Heisenberg

Verified writer

  • Expert in: Sociology

writer

+ 120 experts online

By clicking “Check Writers’ Offers”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy . We’ll occasionally send you promo and account related email

No need to pay just yet!

Related Essays

2 pages / 985 words

2 pages / 1005 words

3 pages / 1591 words

3 pages / 1484 words

Remember! This is just a sample.

You can get your custom paper by one of our expert writers.

121 writers online

Still can’t find what you need?

Browse our vast selection of original essay samples, each expertly formatted and styled

Related Essays on Social Norms

Implicit bias, an intrinsic component of human cognition, holds a significant role in shaping our attitudes, beliefs, and actions without conscious awareness. This essay delves deeply into the definition of implicit bias, [...]

Social norms are the unwritten rules that govern behavior in a society. They dictate how individuals should act, dress, and speak in various situations. These norms are essential for maintaining order and cohesion within a [...]

Social norms are the unwritten rules that govern behavior in society, dictating how individuals should act in various situations. These norms are essential for maintaining order and cohesion within a community, as they provide a [...]

Social norms are an integral part of society, shaping the way individuals behave and interact with one another. These norms are the unwritten rules that govern our actions, beliefs, and values, and they vary across different [...]

While many of us may like to believe that our society today as we know it has advanced in many ways beyond the thoughts and beliefs of the colonial era and the time of slavery, this is unfortunately not the case. In many ways, [...]

Informal norms are unwritten rules and expectations that guide social behavior within a community or society. While formal norms are explicitly stated laws and regulations, informal norms are more subtle and often based on [...]

Related Topics

By clicking “Send”, you agree to our Terms of service and Privacy statement . We will occasionally send you account related emails.

Where do you want us to send this sample?

By clicking “Continue”, you agree to our terms of service and privacy policy.

Be careful. This essay is not unique

This essay was donated by a student and is likely to have been used and submitted before

Download this Sample

Free samples may contain mistakes and not unique parts

Sorry, we could not paraphrase this essay. Our professional writers can rewrite it and get you a unique paper.

Please check your inbox.

We can write you a custom essay that will follow your exact instructions and meet the deadlines. Let's fix your grades together!

Get Your Personalized Essay in 3 Hours or Less!

We use cookies to personalyze your web-site experience. By continuing we’ll assume you board with our cookie policy .

  • Instructions Followed To The Letter
  • Deadlines Met At Every Stage
  • Unique And Plagiarism Free

social norms essay

IMAGES

  1. Breaking Social Norms Essay

    social norms essay

  2. Essay On Social Norms And Values Free Essay Example

    social norms essay

  3. Breaking Social Norms Essay Example

    social norms essay

  4. Social Norm Examples

    social norms essay

  5. Social Norms Essay Example

    social norms essay

  6. Traditions and Social Norms in Today’s Society Which are Being

    social norms essay

VIDEO

  1. Обществознание 8 класс (Урок№4

  2. Breaking Social Norms (Sociology Project)

  3. social norms their characteristics and its types in detail (Mission with vision)

  4. Социальные нормы и отклоняющееся поведение

  5. 5.4.1 Понятие социальных ценностей и норм

  6. 3.4 Социальные нормы

COMMENTS

  1. Social Norms Essay

    Social Norms In Sociology. To start, I will discuss what social norms are. Societal norms are both unwritten informal rules that are accepted by people and written formal rules that are strictly enforced laws, of how people should carry themselves (Keirns, et al., 2016). Social norms are part of the socialization process.

  2. Social Norms and Their Violations

    Social norms shape the behaviors and actions of individuals to a considerable extent. They represent an unwritten policy concerning the expected human behavior. Social norms are fundamental in promoting order and control in society. These rules reflect the behavioral patterns of members of a certain group. The application of these norms can be ...

  3. Social Norms In Society: [Essay Example], 654 words

    Social Norms in Society. Social norms are an integral part of society, shaping the way individuals behave and interact with one another. These norms are the unwritten rules that govern our actions, beliefs, and values, and they vary across different cultures, communities, and time periods. In this essay, we will explore the concept of social ...

  4. Norms And Social Norm: [Essay Example], 854 words GradesFixer

    Norms can be explicit or implicit, written or unwritten, and they vary across cultures and communities. These social norms play a crucial role in maintaining social order, cohesion, and harmony. In this essay, we will explore the concept of norms and social norms, their significance in society, and the ways in which they shape our behavior.

  5. PDF Social norms and social influence

    Social norms are the foundation of culture, of language, of social interaction, cuisine, love, marriage, play, prejudice, economic exchange and traffic control. The elements of this list are fundamental to human life; the list is endless. The human organism is built for social norms. The foundations of social norms in imitation and social learn ...

  6. 94 Social Norms Essay Topic Ideas & Examples

    The struggle to violate a social norm and the sharp reaction to it is due to the culture that exists in that particular setting. Social Norms in "A Streetcar Named Desire" by Tennessee Williams. In Blanche's opinion, beauty is the true value of a woman since it enables her to win recognition of men.

  7. PDF Essays on Social Norms

    2. 3. Essays on Social Norms. by Minjae Kim. Submitted to the Sloan School of Management on April 19, 2018, in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Management. ABSTRACT. The first essay addresses why people might conform to norms that they do not endorse.

  8. Social Norms

    Social norms, the informal rules that govern behavior in groups and societies, have been extensively studied in the social sciences. Anthropologists have described how social norms function in different cultures (Geertz 1973), sociologists have focused on their social functions and how they motivate people to act (Durkheim 1895 [1982], 1950 [1957]; Parsons 1937; Parsons & Shils 1951; James ...

  9. PDF Defining Social Norms and Related Concepts

    A social network refers to the connections, interactions and relationships between individuals.11Social networks exist both in person and virtually, and are often formed with others having similar interests or identities, and for a range of reasons, such as social, economic or political purposes. Reference groups are part of the social networks ...

  10. Social norms and social influence

    Social norms are the foundation of culture, of language, of social interaction, cuisine, love, marriage, play, prejudice, economic exchange and traffic control. The elements of this list are fundamental to human life; the list is endless. The human organism is built for social norms. The foundations of social norms in imitation and social ...

  11. Essays on social norms

    The first essay addresses why people might conform to norms that they do not endorse. One explanation is pluralistic ignorance: when everyone appears to endorse a norm, even nonendorsers will conform so as to feign their commitment to the group's values, thereby exacerbating the misperception.

  12. Essays on Social Norms

    Social Norms in Frankenstein by Mary Shelley. Essay grade: Satisfactory. 2 pages / 1058 words. Humans are emotional and fears, anxieties, desires, and ultimately become monsters. In all societies, people organize themselves and others into groups or categories based on the social classes, physical features, languages, religions, etc. Along with ...

  13. Social Norm Essays: Examples, Topics, & Outlines

    Social Norm Experiment: Scenario 6 -- Facing the rong ay in an Elevator Solomon Asch's Conformity Experiments during the 1950s demonstrated how much individual opinion and even perception of reality can be influenced by others (Gerrig & Zimbardo 2009, 577-579). In the original series of experiments, Asch tested subjects by presenting with a perceptual question that should have been very easy ...

  14. Why do people follow social norms?

    Abstract. Norms prescribe how to make decisions in social situations and play a crucial role in sustaining cooperative relationships and coordinating collective action. However, following norms often requires restricting behavior, demanding to curtail selfishness, or suppressing personal goals. This raises the question why people adhere to norms.

  15. 102 Examples of Social Norms (List)

    Examples of Social Norms. Greeting people when you see them. Saying "thank you" for favors. Holding the door open for others. Standing up when someone else enters the room. Offering to help someone carrying something heavy. Speaking quietly in public places. Waiting in line politely. Respecting other people's personal space.

  16. Social norms and how they impact behaviour

    In another example of a successful social norms intervention, Nolan and colleagues 2 found that household energy use was reduced the most when people were presented with a descriptive normative ...

  17. Breaking Social Norms in Sociology: [Essay Example], 585 words

    Breaking social norms is a valuable tool for sociologists to study the underlying dynamics of society. By intentionally violating these norms, researchers can gain insights into how norms are formed, how power operates in social interactions, and how individuals exercise agency in shaping their behavior. This research can help us understand the ...

  18. Social Norms

    Paper Type: 1300 Word Essay Examples. Conformity is a pervasive aspect of human behavior, shaping our actions, beliefs, and attitudes in alignment with prevailing social norms. This phenomenon is integral to our daily lives, influencing everything from speech and dress codes to eating habits.

  19. The dynamic nature of social norms: New perspectives on norm

    Social norms can be defined as implicit or explicit rules or principles that are understood by members of a group and that guide and ... theoretical perspectives (e.g., in the realm of social identity, person perception, fairness, culture, religion), papers in this special issue illustrate how individual differences (e.g., identification ...

  20. Much Ado About Nothing Social Norms

    The Elizabethan era set many social standards and expectations controlling how society lived. In Shakespeare's play Much Ado About Nothing made in 1598, this idea is reflected, controlling how characters are perceived in the play. Although some characters oppose these stereotypes, challenging the social norms of society within this period ...

  21. Breaking Social Norms Essay

    Breaking Social Norms Essay. This essay sample was donated by a student to help the academic community. Papers provided by EduBirdie writers usually outdo students' samples. Our society is ruled by a massive number of social norms that we follow in our everyday lives. Social norms are these unwritten rules put into place by the society around ...

  22. Breaking Social Norms: Examples: [Essay Example], 501 words

    Another example of breaking social norms is the concept of gender roles. In many societies, there are specific expectations for how individuals should behave based on their gender. Breaking these norms can lead to backlash and criticism. For example, a man wearing makeup or a woman pursuing a traditionally male-dominated career can challenge ...

  23. Social norms and social practices

    Abstract. Theories of social norms frequently define social norms in terms of individuals' beliefs and preferences, and so afford individual beliefs and preferences conceptual priority over social norms. I argue that this treatment of social norms is unsustainable. Taking Bicchieri's theory as an exemplar of this approach, I argue, first ...

  24. Norm Violation in Sociology: [Essay Example], 1203 words

    Social Norms Essay: Research Methodology. To ensure accurate results, I selected various locations and times to conduct the experiment. It was essential to choose public restrooms with high attendance rates to collect sufficient data for analysis. The experiment itself was straightforward. I entered the men's restroom and observed the reaction ...