Conflict Analysis and International Relations

Cite this chapter.

Book cover

  • Karin Aggestam  

Part of the book series: Palgrave Studies in Political Psychology Series ((PSPP))

883 Accesses

3 Citations

Conflict analysis concerns the systematic study of the causes, actors, processes and resolution of conflicts around the globe. It draws upon a number of disciplines and strives to be conflict sensitive while generating relevant suggestions on how to manage and resolve conflict. The broad focus of conflict analysis is also reflected in the multitude of methodological approaches which are utilised (see, e.g., Druckman, 2005). This diversity partly relates to the differences in the overarching purpose of research. For instance, some studies strive to predict conflict behaviour and attitudes with the utilisation of game theory and/or simulation (Colaresi and Thompson, 2002; Maoz and Mor, 1996). Other studies aim for policy relevance and to bridge the theory-practice divide (Fisher, 2009). In such studies, structured focused comparison and/or single case studies methods are frequently used not only for theory advancement of conflict analysis, but also for generic and normative prescriptions. For instance, it may concern when and how specific conflict-resolution strategies are considered most efficient to be applied during a conflict cycle. Finally, a growing number of studies use ethnography and narrative as methods to unravel the complexities between identity politics, specific contextual features of conflict and global structures (Auerbach, 2009; Jutila et al., 2008; Nesbitt-Larking and Kinnvall, 2012). In short, the fields of research and practice of conflict analysis are vast (Monroe et al., 2009).

  • Foreign Policy
  • International Relation
  • Belief System
  • Restorative Justice
  • Political Elite

These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
  • Durable hardcover edition

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Unable to display preview.  Download preview PDF.

Abu-Nimer, M. ed. (2001) Reconciliation, Justice, and Co-existence. Theory and Practice . Lanham: Lexington Books.

Google Scholar  

Aggestam, K. (2009) ‘Diplomacy and Peacemaking in Transition’. In: Aggestam, K. and Magnus Jerneck, M. eds. Diplomacy in Theory and Practice . Malmö: Liber Publishers.

Aggestam, K. (2013) ‘Recognitional Just Peace’. In: Aggestam, K. and Björkdahl, A. eds. Rethinking Peacebuilding: The Quest for Just Peace in the Middle East and Western Balkans . London: Routledge.

Anastasiou, H. (2009) ‘Encountering Nationalism: The Contribution of Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution’. In: Sandole, D., Byrne, S., Sandole-Staroste, I. and Senehi, J. eds. Handbook of Conflict Analysis and Resolution . London and New York: Routledge.

Aronoff, M. J. and Aronoff, Y. S. (1996) ‘Explaining domestic influences on current foreign policy: The peace negotiations’. Brown Journal of World Affairs , 83(3): 83–102.

Atran, S. and Axelrod, R. (2008) ‘Reframing sacred values’. Negotiation Journal , 24(3): 221–246.

Article   Google Scholar  

Auerbach, Y. (1986) ‘Turning point decisions: A cognitive-dissonance analysis of conflict reduction in Israel-West German relations’. Political Psychology , 7(3): 533–550.

Auerbach, Y. (2009) ‘The reconciliation pyramid — A narrative-based framework for analyzing identity conflicts’. Political Psychology , 30(2): 291–318.

Avruch, K. and Mitchell, C. (2013) Conflict Resolution and Human Needs: Linking Theory and Practice . London: Routledge.

Azar E. & Burton J. (eds.) (1986) International Conflict Resolution , Boulder: Lynne Rienner Publishers.

Bar-Tal, D. (2000) ‘From intractable conflict through conflict resolution to reconciliation. Psychological analysis’. Political Psychology , 21(2): 351–365.

Bar-Tal, D. (2004) ‘The necessity of observing real life situations: Palestinian-Israeli violence as a laboratory of learning about social behavior’. European Journal of Social Psychology , 34: 1–25.

Bar-Tal, D. and Bennick, G. (2004) ‘The Nature of Reconciliation as an Outcome and as a Process’. In: Bar-Siman-Tov, Y. ed. From Conflict Resolution to Reconciliation . London: Oxford University Press.

Brecher, M. (1972) The Foreign Policy System of Israel . London: Oxford University Press.

Broome, B. (2009) ‘Building Relational Empathy through an Interactive Design Process’. In: Sandole, D., Byrne, S., Sandole-Staroste, I. and Senehi, J. eds. Handbook of Conflict Analysis and Resolution . London and New York: Routledge.

Brändström, A., Bynander, F. and t’Hart, P. (2004) ‘Governing by looking back: Historical analogies and crisis management’. Public Administration , 82(1): 191–210.

Burton, J. (1993) ‘Conflict Resolution as a Political Philosophy’. In: Sandole, D. J. D and van der Merwe, H. eds. Conflict Resolution Theory and Practice. Integration and Application . Manchester: Manchester University Press.

Burton, J. (1995) ‘Conflict Provention as a Political System’. In: Vasquez, J. A., Turner Johnson, J., Jaffe, S. and Stamato, L. eds. Beyond Confrontation. Learning Conflict Resolution in the Post-Cold War Era . Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.

Clark, J. N. (2008) ‘The three Rs: Retributive justice, restorative justice, and reconciliation’. Contemporary Justice Review , 11(4): 331–350.

Colaresi, M. and Thompson, W. (2002) ‘Strategic rivalries, protracted conflict, and crisis escalation’. Journal of Peace Research , 39: 263–287.

Coleman, P. T. (2006) ‘Intractable Conflict’. In: Deutsch, M., Coleman, P. and Marcus, E. eds. The Handbook on Conflict Resolution: Theory and Practice (2nd edition). San Francisco: Jossey Bass.

Cook-Huffman, C. (2009) ‘The Role of Identity in Conflict’. In: Sandole, D., Byrne, S., Sandole-Staroste, I. and Senehi, J. eds. Handbook of Conflict Analysis and Resolution . London and New York: Routledge.

Dayton, B. and Kriesberg (2010) Conflict Transformation and Peacebuilding. Moving from Violence to Sustainable Peace . London: Routledge.

Deutsch, M. (2006) ‘Justice and Conflict’. In: Deutsch, M., Coleman, P. and Marcus, E. eds. The Handbook on Conflict Resolution: Theory and Practice (2nd edition). San Francisco: Jossey Bass.

Devine-Wright, P. (2003) ‘A Theoretical Overview of Memory and Conflict’. In: Cairns, E. and Roe, M. D. eds. The Role of Memory in Ethnic Conflict . Basingstoke: Palgrave.

Druckman, D. (2005) Doing Research. Methods of Inquiry for Conflict Analysis . Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications.

Edkins, J. (2003) Trauma and the Memory of Politics . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Book   Google Scholar  

Festinger, L. (1957) A Theory of Cognitive Dissonance . Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Fisher, R. J. (2009) ‘Interactive Conflict Resolution: Dialogue, Conflict Analysis, and Problemsolving’. In: Sandole, D., Byrne, S., Sandole-Staroste, I. and Senehi, J. eds. Handbook of Conflict Analysis and Resolution . London and New York: Routledge.

George, A. L. (1969) ‘The “operational code”: A neglected approach to the study of political leaders and decision-making’. International Studies Quarterly , 13(2): 190–222.

Hammack, P. L. (2008) ‘Narrative and the cultural psychology of identity’. Personality and Social Psychology Review , 12(3): 222–247.

Hammack, P. L. and Pelicki, A. (2012) ‘Narrative as a root metaphor for political psychology’. Political Psychology , 33(1): 75–103.

Heradstveit, D. (1979) The Arab-Israeli Conflict: Psychological Obstacles to Peace . Oslo: Universitetsforlaget.

Herrmann, R. K., Isernia, P. and Segatti, P. (2009) ‘Attachment to the nation and international relations: Dimensions of identity and their relationship to war and peace’. Political Psychology , 30(5): 721–754.

Hermann T. (2004) Reconciliation: Reflections on the Theoretical and Practical Utility of the Term. In : Bar-Siman-Tov, Yaacov (ed.) From Conflict Resolution to Reconciliation . Oxford University Press.

Hoffman, M. (1995) ‘Defining and evaluating success: Facilitative problem-solving workshops in an interconnected context’. Paradigms. The Kent Journal of International Relations , 9(2): 150–167.

Holsti, O. R. (1962) ‘The belief system and national images’. International Studies Quarterly , 13(4): 190–222.

Jabri, V. (1996) Discourses on Violence . Manchester and New York: Manchester University Press.

Jeong, H.-W. (2008) Understanding Conflict and Conflict Analysis . London: Sage Publications.

Jervis, R. (1976) Perception and Misperception in International Politics . Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Jönsson, C. (1990) Communication in International Bargaining . London: Pinter Publishers Ltd.

Jutila, M., Pekhonen, S. and Väyrynen, T. (2008) ‘Resuscitating a discipline: An agenda for critical peace research’. Millennium. Journal of International Studies , 36(3): 623–640.

Kaldor, M. (2001) New and Old Wars . Cambridge: Polity Press.

Kaldor, M. (2013) ‘In defence of new wars’. Stability: International Journal of Security and Development , 2(1): 1–16.

Kaplowitz, N. (1990) ‘National self-images, perception of enemies, and conflict strategies: Psychopolitical dimensions of international relations’. Political Psychology , 11(1): 39–81.

Kalyvas, S. N. (2001) ‘“New” and “old” civil wars: A valid distinction?’. World Politics , 54: 99–118.

Kelman, H. (1992) ‘Informal Mediation by the Scholar/Practitioner’. In: Bercovitch, J. and Rubin, J. Z. eds. Mediation in International Relations. Multiple Approaches to Conflict Management . New York: St. Martin’s Press.

Kelman, H. (2009) ‘A Social-Psychological Approach to Conflict Analysis and Resolution’. In: Sandole, D., Byrne, S., Sandole-Staroste, I. and Senehi, J. eds. Handbook of Conflict Analysis and Resolution . London and New York: Routledge.

Kinnvall, C. (2004) ‘Globalization and religious nationalism: Self, identity, and the search for ontological security’. Political Psychology , 25(5): 741–767.

Korostelina, K. (2009) ‘Identity Conflicts: Models of Dynamics and Early Warning’. In: Sandole, D., Byrne, S., Sandole-Staroste, I. and Senehi, J. eds. Handbook of Conflict Analysis and Resolution . London and New York: Routledge.

Kriesberg, L. (1989) ‘Transforming Conflicts in the Middle East and Central Europe’. In: Kriesberg, L., Northrup, T. A. and Thorson, S. J. eds. Intractable Conflicts and their Transformation . Syracuse: Syracuse University Press.

Larson, D. W. (1985) Origins of Containment. A Psychological Explanation . Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Larson, D. W. (1994) ‘The role of belief systems and schemas in foreign policy decision-making’. Political Psychology , 15(1): 17–33.

Lebow, N. R. (1981) Between Peace and War: The Nature of International Crisis . Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.

Lederach, J. P. (2005) The Moral Imagination. The Art and Soul of Building Peace . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Lupovici, A. (2012) ‘Ontological dissonance, clashing identities, and Israel’s unilateral steps towards the Palestinians’. Review of International Studies , 38(4): 809–833.

Maoz, Z. and Mor, B. (1996) ‘Enduring rivalries: The early years’. International Political Science Review , 17(2): 141–160.

Margalit, A. (2010) On Compromise and Rotten Compromises . Princeton: Princeton University Press.

McDonald, J. W. and Bendahmane, D. B. eds. (1987) Conflict Resolution: Track Two Diplomacy . Washington, DC: Foreign Service Institute, US Department of State.

Menkel-Meadow, C. (2007) ‘Restorative justice: What is it and does it work?’ Georgetown University Law Center, Annual Review of Law and Social Science , 3: 161–187.

Monroe, K., Chiu, W., Martin, A. and Portman, B. (2009) ‘What is political psychology?’ Perspectives on Politics , 7(4): 859–882.

Montville, J. (2001) ‘Justice and the Burdens of History, Reconciliation, Justice and Co-existence’. In: Abu-Nimer, M. ed. Reconciliation, Justice, and Co-existence. Theory and Practice . Lanham: Lexington Books.

Montville, J. (2010) ‘Track-Two diplomacy’. In: Young, N. J. ed. The Oxford International Encyclopedia of Peace . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Murithi, T. (2009) The Ethics of Peacebuilding . Edinbourgh: Edinbourgh University Press.

Nesbitt-Larking, P. and Kinnvall, C. (2012) ‘The discursive frames of political psychology’. Political Psychology , 33(1): 45–59.

Newman, E. (2004) ‘The “new wars” debate: A historical perspective is needed’. Security Dialogue , 35(2): 173–189.

Rapoport, A. (1974) Fight, Games, and Debates . Ann Arbour: University of Michigan Press.

Ripley, B. (1995) ‘Cognition, Culture, and Bureaucratic Politics’. In: Neack, L., Hey, J. A. K. and Haney, P. J. eds. Foreign Policy Analysis. Continuity and Change in Its Second Generation . Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, Inc.

Rothman, J. (1997) Resolving Identity-Based Conflict: In Nations, Organizations, and Communities . San Francisco: Jossey-Bass Publishers.

Ross, M. H. (2004) ‘Ritual and the Politics of Reconciliation’. In: Bar-Siman-Tov, Y. ed. From Conflict Resolution to Reconciliation . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Rousoux, V. (2009) ‘Reconciliation as a Peace-Building Process: Scope and Limits’. In: Bercovitch, J., Kremenyuk, V. and Zartman, I. W. eds. The Sage Handbook of Conflict Resolution . London: Sage Publications.

Rubinstein, R. (2009) ‘Conflict Resolution in an Age of Empire: New Challenges to an Emerging Field’. In: Sandole, D., Byrne, S., Sandole-Staroste, I. and Senehi, J. eds. Handbook of Conflict Analysis and Resolution . London and New York: Routledge.

Ryan, S. (2009) ‘Conflict Transformation: Reason to be Modest’. In: Sandole, D., Byrne, S., Sandole-Staroste, I. and Senehi, J. eds. Handbook of Conflict Analysis and Resolution . London and New York: Routledge.

Schaap, A. (2008) ‘Reconciliation as ideology and politics’. Australian Journal of International Relations , 15(2): 249–264.

Schelling, T. C. (1960) The Strategy of Conflict . Cambridge and London: Harvard University (Sixteenth printing 1997).

Snyder, G. and Diesing, P. (1977) Conflict among Nations: Bargaining, Decision Making and System Structure in International Crises . Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Staub, E. (2010) Other Elements of Reconciliation: Collective Memory, Shared History and Justice . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Stein, J. G. (1996) ‘Image, Identity, and Conflict Resolution’. In: Crocker, C. A., Hampson, F. O. and All, P. eds. Managing Global Chaos. Sources of and Responses to International Conflict . Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace Press.

Tidwell, A. C. (1998) Conflict Resolved? A Critical Assessment of Conflict Resolution . London and New York: Pinter.

Strömbom L. (2010) Revisiting the Past. Israeli Identity, Thick Recognition and Conflict Transformation , Lund, Media-Tryck.

Thompson, J. (2009) ‘Apology, historical obligations and the ethics of memory’. Memory Studies , 2(2): 195–210.

Thompson, L., Nadler, J. and Lount, R. (2006) ‘Judgmental Biases in Conflict Resolution and How to Overcome Them’. In: Deutsch, M., Coleman, P. and Marcus, E. eds. The Handbook on Conflict Resolution: Theory and Practice (2nd edition). San Francisco: Jossey Bass.

Väyrynen, T. (1995) ‘Going beyond similarity: The role of the facilitator in problemsolving workshop conflict resolution’. Paradigms. The Kent Journal of International Relations , 9(2): 71–85.

Vertzberger, Y. I. (1990) The World in Their Minds. Information Processing, Cognition, and Perception in Foreign Policy Decisionmaking . Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Volkan, V. (2006) Killing in the Name of Identity. A Study of Bloody Conflict . Charlottesville: Pitchstone Publishing.

Volkan, V. (1997) Bloodlines: From Ethnic Pride to Ethnic Terrorism , New York, Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

Welch, D. (1995) Justice and the Genesis of War . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Download references

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Editor information

Editors and affiliations.

Department of Political Science, Huron University College, Canada

Paul Nesbitt-Larking

Department of Political Science, Lund University, Sweden

Catarina Kinnvall

Department of Politics, University of Surrey, UK

Tereza Capelos

Graduate School of Social and Behavioural Sciences, Leiden University, The Netherlands

Henk Dekker

Copyright information

© 2014 Karin Aggestam

About this chapter

Aggestam, K. (2014). Conflict Analysis and International Relations. In: Nesbitt-Larking, P., Kinnvall, C., Capelos, T., Dekker, H. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of Global Political Psychology. Palgrave Studies in Political Psychology Series. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-29118-9_9

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-29118-9_9

Publisher Name : Palgrave Macmillan, London

Print ISBN : 978-1-349-67104-5

Online ISBN : 978-1-137-29118-9

eBook Packages : Palgrave Political Science Collection Political Science and International Studies (R0)

Share this chapter

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research

The debates of methodology and methods: reflections on the development of the study of international relations

Review of Economics and Political Science

ISSN : 2631-3561

Article publication date: 12 May 2021

This paper aims to explore the interplay between methods and methodologies in the field of international relations (IR) over the 100 years of its lifetime reflecting on the relationship between the rise of new research methods and the rise of new methodologies.

Design/methodology/approach

This paper looks in retrospect into the field’s great debates using a historiography approach. It maps chronologically the interplay of methods and methodology throughout the stages of the development of the study of IR.

This paper argues that inspite of narratives of triumph being common in the field, the coexistence of competing research methods and methodologies is the defining feature of the field. All theories, all methods and all methodologies have undergone a process of criticism, self-criticism and change. New methodologies have not necessarily accompanied the rise of new research methods in the field.

Originality/value

Drawing a map of the field’s methodologies and methods reveals necessarily its dynamism and its plurality. An honest map of the field is one that highlights not only theoretical differences but also ontological, epistemological and methodological differences embedded in the field’s debates.

  • Research methods
  • Methodology
  • Historiography
  • Post-positivism

Abou Samra, A. (2021), "The debates of methodology and methods: reflections on the development of the study of international relations", Review of Economics and Political Science , Vol. ahead-of-print No. ahead-of-print. https://doi.org/10.1108/REPS-06-2020-0063

Emerald Publishing Limited

Copyright © 2021, Amira Abou Samra.

Published in Review of Economics and Political Science . Published by Emerald Publishing Limited. This article is published under the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY 4.0) licence. Anyone may reproduce, distribute, translate and create derivative works of this article (for both commercial and non-commercial purposes), subject to full attribution to the original publication and authors. The full terms of this licence maybe seen at http://creativecommons.org/licences/by/4.0/legalcode

Introduction

International relations (IR) theorists, especially since the second half of the 20th century, had been inclined to consider concerns over ontology, epistemology and methodology to fall outside the scope of their interest, to be of concern to the field of philosophy ( Hay, 2006 ). Today, however, as IR theory is witnessing its “fourth debate,” quite frequently described as a “metatheoretical debate,” these concerns are no longer dismissible. There is a growing awareness that discussions over methodology have been marginalized in favour of discussions over theories and that this is something that needs to be remedied ( Chernoff, 2007 , p. 2).

This paper argues that learning about the theoretical assumptions, without paying due attention to methodological and methodical aspects behind them, leaves researchers halfway through, either blinded to the plethora of possible alternative ways available to deal with political reality or rather totally unequipped to deal with it. Whilst highlighting the methodological and methodical debates that have been going on in the field, this paper argues that telling the history of the relationship between research methods and methodology is an important alternative way of telling the story of the field debates, leading to the appreciation of deeper differences and similarities between its paradigms and theories and to the answering of important questions about methodological plurality in the field, the meaning of science and future concerns for the study of IR.

Hence, the paper is not concerned with the great debates of the field as such, but rather interested in drawing a historiographical map of field debates in a way that specifically addresses the interplay between methodology and methods, seeking, thereby, to answer a number of questions: If it is common to highlight changes in the research methods of the field by referring to two basic tracks, the traditionalist-behaviouralist-post-behaviouralist track and the positivist, post-positivist track ( Mostafa, 2016 , pp. 57–70; Mosafa, 2010 , pp. 840–846), where do methodologies diverge and converge in these two tracks? What is the relationship between the emergence of new research methods and the emergence of new methodologies in IR? How does literature in the late 1980s exploring a methodological turn in IR ( Little, 1991 , pp. 463–478) differ from literature in 2017 lamenting over an overdue methodological turn ( Kanfo, 2017 )? Do new research methods and new methodologies coexist with old ones? Do they necessarily compete? If methodology is the process of establishing scientific inquiry ( Kaplan, 1964 , pp. 22–24), what impact does the existence of multiple methodologies have on the meaning of science?

For conceptual clarity, methodology and research methods fit into a matrix of interconnected and interrelated concepts as broad as epistemology, ontology, methodology and theory. In philosophical traditions, “ontology” corresponds to the study of being or existence, where the answers to major questions about the relationship between human beings, the universe and nature are reflected upon. The ontology generates a specific view of knowledge, that is, the epistemology. Epistemology answers questions such as: What can we know and what are the sources of knowledge? What is the purpose of knowledge? Is “certain” knowledge ever achievable? Is the development of knowledge and science progressive in nature so that newer theories necessarily carry more knowledge than older ones? The epistemology provides the background foundation for all theorization. Directly derivable from the epistemology are both the ontology of the field and its methodology ( Abul-Fadl, 1994 ; Krauss, 2005 ).

It is important to distinguish between the philosophical understanding of ontology, where ontology as a theory of existence serves as a driver of epistemology, a theory of knowledge and methodology as a process of producing science on the one hand, and between ontology in the understanding of the field of IR, where the word “ontology,” though borrowed from philosophy, stands for the content of political reality in the field, e.g. “identities, individuals, social collectivities, states, regimes, systems, or some combination of the above.” ( Hay, 2006 ). Ontology in social sciences answers also the question of “what is reality,” hence, whether reality has a solid and an independent existence from researchers or whether reality is just “fluid and constructed the result of human perception and claims about it” ( Lacatus et al. , 2015 ).

Methodology is defined by Abraham Kaplan (1964 , pp. 22–24) as “the logic of scientific research”; the process by which science is produced. Kaplan’s definition of methodology is broader, even more neutral, than definitions that, later on, directly link methodology to empiricism, whereby empiricism is a methodology used to “form theoretical claims and to test their empirical implications.” In such a narrow definition of methodology only what is empirically testable, hypotheses that can lend themselves to falsification by being subjected to a test of reality, is science ( Sprinz and Wolinsky-Nahmias, 2004 , p. 4). This definition of methodology is inseparable from a definition of theory that regards theory as a set of assumptions to be tested against reality for accuracy, validity and quality ( Sprinz and Wolinsky-Nahmias, 2004 , p. 4).

In its broad definition, however, methodology refers to a process that produces science. Even if that science is not testable against reality; for so many reasons, amongst which might be the belief that there is no neutral or independent existence of reality that it can be tested against to begin with, as will be furtherly explained throughout the paper.

Ultimately, what one considers as “science” and what one accepts as “theory” are products of what one believes in, epistemologically, ontologically and, by consequence, methodologically.

Methodology produces theories that end up producing or making use of approaches or research methods which answer the question: What are the specific steps that the researcher must follow to get to answer his research question?

This paper is divided into two main parts looking in retrospect into the debates of the field, chronologically mapping the interplay of methods and methodology through the stages of the development of the study of IR. The first part, divided into three sections, tells the story of the development of the study of IR over a time span of around 60 years until the end of the 1970s or mid-1980s which mark the beginning of the “relative” demise of the behaviouralist “hegemony” over the field.

The second part of the paper, divided into three sections, covers the period starting from the relative “demise of the empiricist positivist promise for a cumulative positivist science” in the late-1970s and mid-1980s until our present time ( Little, 1991 , p. 463), asking whether the past four decades have brought along some methodological turn in IR or simply a shift in research methods and techniques.

Part I: traditionalism-behaviouralism-post-behaviouralism

Traditionalism vs. behaviouralism: from the science of advice to the science of grand theories.

The positivist enlightenment project though produced in Europe, flourished and boomed in the USA. Positivism was and still is a dominant feature of the American understanding of social reality ( Smith, 2000 , p. 375). Behaviouralism as a positivist methodological approach to the study of political science had its origins in the USA in the 1920s and 1930s and has been usually associated with the University of Chicago and the works of Charles Merriam ( Grigsby, 2011 , p. 15). Behaviouralism was influenced by behaviourism ( Hafner-Burton et al. , 2017 , pp. S1–S3), a school of psychology reflecting positivism, a “belief in the infinite possibilities of science” and “in the powers of the human mind,” where logic and reason constitute the only source of all certain knowledge ( Herakovic, 1983 , p. 10). In behaviourism, human behaviour can be simplified to the extent that it can be measured in the here and now without any reference to past experiences or inner motives ( Herakovic, 1983 , pp. 70–82). Human behaviour can be observed, monitored and interpreted based on its external features ( Hamati-Ataya, 2012 , pp. 3–4). Behaviourist assumptions were influenced by the “stimulus and response idiom”, and were, hence, advocating that living organisms – be they animals or human beings – interact with all forms of external stimuli in a manner that seems to be quite uniform. Behaviouralism was furtherly influenced by the behaviourist belief that “the same laws that governed the physical world could be applied to human nature,” hence came the appreciation for controlled laboratory experiments and empiricism, where the senses are the main sources of knowledge. Although behaviouralism later on distinguished itself from behaviourism ( Hamati-Ataya, 2012 , pp. 3–4), behaviourism’s impact on social sciences in general and political science in particular could not be mistaken. Behaviourism had already been influential in other social sciences since the past decades of the 19th century ( Davis, 1965 ; Smith, 1989 ). There, “tough minded empiricism overthrew the hegemony of the moral philosophy of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries” and carried along an “epistemic transformation” to social sciences ( Davis, 1965 ; Smith, 1989 ) replacing “absolute sources of truth” with the “boundless belief in the powers of the human mind” ( Herakovic, 1983 , p. 10). This is why the behaviouralist turn in IR was not just a methodological turn, but rather mainly an epistemic turn.

In the field of IR, behaviouralists in the 1950s were propagating to be the missionaries of a “scientific revolution,” endorsing the following set of basic assumptions:

First, IR as an independent social science: Behaviouralism advocates the ability of IR to exist as an independent social science. That advocation stands in deep contrast to a traditional perception of IR as a common/joint research area shared by many fields and sciences – such as philosophy, law, economics and even political science ( Finnegan, 1972 , p. 40). Interestingly, behaviouralism borrowed approaches from other fields such as mathematics, physics, biology, economics, sociology and psychology, hence not only from natural sciences but also form social sciences that were already witnessing a behaviourist turn, fields that traditionalism did not consider as relevant to political science though ( Hamati-Ataya, 2012 , p. 5).

Second, the unity of scientific knowledge: behaviouralists considered IR (as a social science) to be quite similar to the natural sciences, where description, measurement, observation and quantitative, mathematical and statistical tools were essential research tools. Traditionalists rather considered IR to be closer to humanities, closer to literature and philosophy, where analysis and contemplation were key to understanding international reality.

Third, science is value-free: In contrast to the traditional perception in which values are inseparable from science and where, therefore, history, political theory and law are indispensable to the understanding of the international phenomenon ( Chernoff, 2007 , p. 2); behaviouralism promoted the possibility of establishing an objective, value-free science in which researchers play a completely neutral role. The reproducibility of knowledge is a key behaviouralist assumption; just by following the same steps, researchers anywhere can get almost the same results ( El-Hayagna, 2001 , p. 111).

Fourth, the possibility of producing major and general theories in IR: A good theory in traditionalism is to be tested against history, political theory and law ( Chernoff, 2007 , p. 2). Behaviouralism claims a good theory is a simple theory that depicts as “less complex causal mechanisms” as possible. Hence, it relies on measurable variables for explaining, even predicting phenomena under study ( El-Hayagna, 2001 , pp. 83–89).

The behaviouralist-traditionalist divide is much more than a divide over research methods; it is a divide over the appropriate methodology for producing “science,” with some clear epistemological and ontological aspects of divergence that will be furtherly discussed in the following section.

Rise of behaviouralism: a journey not void of criticism

Traditional approaches to thinking about political reality were quite prevalent in political science in the early 20th century ( Druckman et al. , 2006 , p. 627).

The early beginnings of the field in the aftermath of the First World War seemed strongly influenced by the ideas of idealists. The likes of the idealist Wilson were driven by a desire to “guide the conduct of states in their IR (towards a more peaceful world), rather than focusing on the actual behaviour of states” ( Hellman, 2011 , p. 18). This explains why the study of IR from an idealist perspective was guided by an interest in political philosophy, international law and diplomacy, the approaches quite familiar to traditionalism ( Hellman, 2011 , p. 18).

Behaviourialism in the field of IR had many critics along the process of its relative rise – Hedley Bull and Stanley Hoffman just to name a few ( Hamati-Ataya, 2012 , p. 17).

Some criticized the fact that behaviouralist studies overlooked cultural diversity and ignored the richness of human experience ( Dyer and Mangasarian, 1989 , p. XVII).

Some criticized behaviouralist claims about the existence of value-neutral science, especially given the growing tendency to equate “observation” with “quantification.” Although behaviourialism did not completely displace values from scientific research, it limited its study to the empirical manifestations of values. An interest for values in a normative sense was relegated to the realm of political philosophy ( Hamati-Ataya, 2012 , pp. 7–10).

Growingly, some warned against the dangers of being “attached to spurious statistical and mathematical correlations” drawing, therewith, the attention to the importance of “testing sophisticated statistical methods” for “real correlations, questioning the significance of these correlations in the absence of human judgement to evaluate them” ( Forward, 1971 , pp. 18–20).

Strikingly, some behaviouralists seemed to struggle with their own behaviouralism. They complained about the lack of data and the confidentiality of many aspects of relations between states. They struggled with the large number of variables affecting IR and with the absence of a clear classification for them. They even complained about cultural and social differences they encountered whilst studying states, a discovery that seemed to impede their pursuit of general laws ( Davis, 1965 , pp. 15–16).

Obviously behaviouralism was not walking its way of empirical political analysis in the absence of research difficulties or amidst general satisfaction. Behaviourialists – in a way maybe comparable to post-positivists today – complained even about their inability to communicate easily with decision-making circles and to influence them ( Forward, 1971 , p. 20).

But the criticisms of behaviouralism – from Europe mainly and sometimes from within the USA itself – did not prevent the spread of behaviouralism, even in Europe ( Hamati-Ataya, 2012 , pp. 6–7).

Although behaviouralism – as previously mentioned – was mainly a product of an American social and political context ( Hamati-Ataya, 2012 , p. 2) and was originally loaded with epistemological, ontological and methodological claims driven from the particularity of positivist enlightenment ( Herakovic, 1983 , p. 10), the traditional-behaviouralist debate – most probably under the influence of the behaviouralist disinterest in philosophy – was usually presented as a debate over appropriate research methods, rather than a debate over the appropriate scientific methodology or the philosophy of science itself. The debate ignored the questions of what constitutes science and whether social sciences have a distinct nature from natural sciences, questions that remained vibrant in the field of philosophy at that time ( Little, 1991 , p. 468).

Looking in retrospect, however, it makes a lot of sense to talk about behaviouralist methodology, not only behaviouralist methods, although the advocation that behaviouralism is charged with epistemological, ontological and methodological content was not that common during the rounds of traditional-behaviouralist debate.

According to Richard Little (1991) , the methodological difference between traditionalists and behaviouralists – though existing since the very beginning – remained unexplored in the field of IR at least until Kenneth Waltz introduced his neo-realist theory in the 1970s ( Little, 1991 , p. 446). The following section explains this statement. The section revolves around the relationship between behaviouralism and realism on the one hand and behaviouralism and neo-realism on the other hand and how the emergence of neo-realism influenced the methodological and methodic debate taking place in the field of IR.

Behaviouralism and realism: the joint journey

With the end of the Second World War, the field became more receptive to realist assumptions. To realism, some attribute the credit for shifting the study of IR from the “science of international values and ethics” – that many have lost their faith in as a result of the Second World War experience – to the “science of studying power and interest” ( Badran, 2000 , pp. 71–72). This obviously was not only implying an ontological shift, moving away from the study of what ought to be to the study of what really is. It was implying an epistemological shift from transcendental meanings of right and wrong, good and bad to a man-centred definition of interests and morality. Many of the realists advocated the need for a general explanatory theory of IR ( Forward, 1971 ; Davis, 1965 ; Hamati-Ataya, 2012 ). Behaviouralism, therefore, was highly compatible with the realist needs, the former allowed for “the pursuance of Realism’s scientific aspirations with the emerging methods and techniques of the age” ( Hamati-Ataya, 2012 , p. 12). The realist-behaviouralist partnership set the stage for their mutual rise within the field.

Maybe the relative rise of behaviouralism can be explained by the field’s longing for a more predictable international environment that is subjectable to accounts of reason and logic to encounter a dangerous Cold War international environment ( Forward, 1971 , p. 20) or just a by-product of the American victory in the Second World War; just a triumph of the knowledge preferences of the more powerful; saying nothing about the quality or worth of behaviouralism per se . Anyway, many consider the period after the Second World War to be the period of the “second and serious foundation of the discipline” dedicated to the reconstruction of a US-led world order ( Ekkehart Krippendorff, 1987 , p. 57). So, and regardless of possible explanations for that, the behaviouralist empirical studies presented themselves from the 1950s onward as the only possessors of a “scientific methodology” in IR ( Chernoff, 2007 , pp. 79–130). Studies sometimes even still refer to behaviouralism as the “scientific approach” to the study of IR, a label that might misleadingly suggest to the unexperienced reader that only behaviouralism is capable of producing “scientific” knowledge in the field.

Under the behaviouralist-realist collaboration, many research methods/approaches were introduced to the study of IR, amongst the most famous of which are rational choice methods such as the game theory, the decision-making approach in foreign policy, etc., mainly oriented towards the study of great power politics with special emphasis on questions of war and military conflict ( Forward, 1971 ).

Of particular importance is the shift in the thinking about the study of IR brought along by Kenneth Waltz (1979) . Waltz, arguably a behaviouralist himself ( Dolan, 2014 , p. 59), directed serious criticism to behaviouralists.

Waltz’ theory revolved around the assumption that anarchy restricts the behaviour of states, forcing them to adopt a conflictual-competitive attitude in a way that reproduces this anarchy over and over and guarantees the continuity of the state system itself. Waltz claimed that the global failure to develop a general IR theory is explicable by the failure of IR theorists to understand this methodological background from which all theories and approaches should depart. To Waltz, his neo-realist systems theory was not just a theory, it was the only viable methodology in IR.

Already as early as the 1970s and 1980s, Waltz’s theory came under scrutiny, especially with the emergence of neo-liberalism and neo-Marxism. The neoliberal theory criticized Waltz’s insistence on ignoring non-competitive forms of relations between states such as those embodied in developments of international law and international institutions ( Little, 1991 , pp. 463–466). On its part, neo-versions of Marxism mainly criticized the claims of systems theory that political power was distributed almost equally between states, because these claims remained oblivious to power relations between different social groups ( Linklater, 1986 , pp. 301–312). These criticisms set the stage for what will become known as the neo-realist, neo-liberal, neo-Marxist debate and later on as the inter-paradigm debate ( Hoffman, 1989 , pp. 60–61), embracing theoretical plurality in the field ( Little, 1991 , p. 463). Interestingly, some of the most prominent neoliberal and neo-Marxist theories were behaviouralist theories, the neoliberal institutionalism and the neo-Marxist Wallerstein’s world-system theory are but examples.

More importantly, in opposition to Waltz’s claim of being in possession of the only scientific methodology, some studies in the field of IR began to raise doubts – finally explicitly – about what the philosophy underlying knowledge in the field of IR should be, whether the field had ever actually been comparable to natural sciences with static laws built in the structure of the universe itself, whether IR was not rather similar to humanities ( Ferguson and Mansbach, 1988 , pp. 656–657). These criticisms were directly targeting the positivist understanding of the world underlying the behaviouralist project and its theoretical advocates – be they neo-realist, neo-liberal or neo-Marxist, reopening, therewith, the way for history, political thought, culture and values to influence the study of IR ( Badran, 2000 , pp. 69–96).

It is important to note that the failure to explain and predict the end of the Cold War was not the only shortcoming of Waltz’s theory. Reality kept surprising neo-realists, whose theory could not later on explain things as major as the continued existence of NATO, inspite of the end of the Cold War ( McCalla, 1996 , pp. 445–475) or developments in the integration process of the European Union.

Theoretical promises to provide exhaustive answers were not fulfilled even in the case of a theory as popular as Waltz’s, declaring, thereby, that realism cannot become a “methodology” for studying IR as Waltz wanted for it to be, but more importantly declaring the “demise of the empiricist positivist promise for a cumulative behavioural(ist) science” ( Little, 1991 , p. 463).

The accumulated criticism to the behaviouralist scientific project would acquire sometimes the title of “post-behaviouralist revolution” ( Hoffman, 1989 , p. 60), revolting against some essential behaviouralist assumptions:

Some post-behaviouralist studies criticized the marginalization of history, the history of the West and the history of peoples around the world in a way that impoverished “the content, the perspectives and tools of IR theory” ( Ekkehart Krippendorff, 1987 , p. 28).

Moreover, some studies criticized the marginalization of normative theorizing in IR, the deliberate neglection of nonmaterial aspects of international politics. For example, the English school would direct serious criticism to the absence of “normative inquiry into the relationship between order and justice,” and social constructivism would complain about the negligence of the role of norms in shaping states’ identities and interests ( Reus-Smit , 2009a, 2009b , p. 66).

Worth noting also is how some studies criticised behaviouralist claims of science being value free and produced early attempts at highlighting some relationship between knowledge and interests by criticizing an American hegemony over the field. Some noted that behaviouralist IR theorizing managed to make the behaviour of the USA become a standard and everyone became dedicated to “justify the unique and frightening accumulation of power in conjunction with the world mission of the United States of America,” rather than challenge or even criticize it ( Ekkehart Krippendorff, 1987 , p. 28).

Post-behaviouralist criticisms to behaviouralism seemed to reiterate many of the traditionalist concerns about the utility and quality of behaviouralist theorizing in IR. However, advocating these criticisms were now several separate theories that began to emerge throughout the late 1970s, 1980s and 1990s: the English school, the postmodern theory, the social constructivist theory, the feminist theory, etc. These theories would gradually line up in the face of the three theories of the inter-paradigm debate. The latter would collectively be called the traditional theories or the mainstream theories of IR ( Sprinz and Wolinsky-Nahmias, 2004 , p. 5). This would leave the field in an unprecedented state of – basically ontological and methodic – fluidity far from being able to agree on the core aspects of the international study such as the main actors, the main issues or even the nature of international processes as vital as globalization itself, growingly realizing that the mainstream theories in the field were incapable of catching up with the complexity of reality and its rapidly changing nature ( Mostafa, 2016 , pp. 70–98).

Criticisms would evolve to produce two different calls in terms of methods and methodology. The first call will defend and retain the positivist character of the field, opening up only to a plurality of research methods, whereas the second call will defend the need for a completely new research attitude towards IR, advocating a post-positivist methodological turn in IR. In the following part, these two calls and the ensuing developments will be tackled in some detail.

Part II: from post-behaviouralism to post-positivism

Easy way out: a call for reconciliation between research methods.

Early responses to criticism to behaviouralist approaches came in the form of calls for “reconciliation” between quantitative – using tools such as statistical analysis, regression coefficients, simple mathematical calculations – and qualitative approaches to international political analysis – using tools such as event analysis, case study, content analysis, interviews, comparisons, etc. ( Mahoney and Goertz, 2006 , pp. 227–228) ( Boassen, 1991 , pp. 192–207), acknowledging some of the analytical shortcomings of quantification and accepting a degree of plurality of research methods in the field. Here, shortcomings of behaviouralism were addressed by responses at the level of research methods, rather than the level of methodology.

Obviously, quantitative and qualitative studies were still supposed to “worship the same (positivist) God,” where science is all about testable observation, even if they disagreed on smaller goals, qualitative studies producing “cause of effect explanations” and quantitative studies producing “effect of cause explanations” ( Mahoney and Goertz, 2006 , pp. 227–228).

A similar conclusion was reached by Sprinz and Wolinsky-Nahmias who believed “methodological pluralism” became a necessity ( Sprinz and Wolinsky-Nahmias, 2004 , pp. 7–8). It is important to note that their reference to methodology is closer in meaning to “approaches or research methods,” rather than methodology as a process of scientific inquiry. This is because the advocated plurality of quantitative and qualitative approaches remained a plurality within the confines of an understanding of science as testable observation, embodying the logic of causation. Enough proof is that a one-third of studies published in prominent journals were discarded from the analysis of Sprinz and Wolinsky-Nahmia’s study – though calling for methodological plurality – because of being “devoid of scientific methodology,” i.e. because of being descriptive and historical ( Mahoney and Goertz, 2006 , p. 8).

Hence, the emergence of qualitative studies as such did not undermine the positivist epistemology and its related methodology in a way that would justify a real methodological distinction between qualitative and quantitative research. It is important not to confuse the positivist qualitative approaches with the post-positivist qualitative approaches to be discussed later on.

Still in the 21st century, admitting the deficiencies of behaviouralism is not an easy task for its advocates. Rather than criticizing the product of empirical behaviouralism, some explained the failure of behaviouralist studies to provide sober political analysis for major events by the failure of behaviouralist studies to grasp the real essence of experimentation, claiming that behaviouralist studies never really conducted an experimental study “in the sense of controlled manipulation as when a single factor is modified, whilst holding everything else constant,” what they did was rather closer to non-experimental empirical tests far from satisfying the “modern meaning of experimentation” ( Druckman et al. , 2006 , pp. 628–629). Here, behaviouralist studies failed, because they were not behaviouralist enough.

Yet, although the advocates of behaviouralism are obviously still far away from being disenchanted with it, most of them have become disenchanted with the goal of reaching a general theory in IR. Instead, the goals of experimental research – whatever the definition of experimentation – have become much more modest serving three purposes: searching for facts to “adjucate disputes” in cases in which studies seem to reach contradictory results, to test the accuracy of certain theoretical assumptions and to advise the political leadership ( Druckman et al. , 2006 , pp. 632–633).

So, new was just a degree of humility about the ability to generalize the conclusions of quantitative studies and a degree of humility about the limited ability of quantitative and experimental research to address some specific research areas, such as the study of civil wars, terrorism or regime stability ( Druckman et al. , 2006 , p. 633), all leading to the above highlighted calls for a reconciliation between qualitative and quantitative approaches.

Anyway, according to this view, the traditional descriptive research methods remain inferior to the quantitative or qualitative research methods that allow the production of studies based on “testable observation.” Traditional approaches pay attention to philosophy, history, values and law in a way that neither these quantitative nor qualitative approaches recognize as “scientific.”

It is not surprising that this very same path will lead today to the so-called “revival of behaviouralism” ( Hamati-Ataya, 2012 , p. 19) or the “new behavioural revolution” ( Hafner-Burton et al. , 2017 , pp. S1–S3) in which contemporary behaviouralism is becoming more modest about the formulation of general theories, is becoming more aware of psychological influences on rationalization, is providing alternatives to or complementing rational choice models and is shifting its goal to the explanation of “the causes and consequences of heterogeneity across actors, including (deviation) from rationalist expectations” ( Hafner-Burton et al. , 2017 ; Mintz, 2007 ) rather than searching for similarities. This explains the interest of contemporary behaviouralists in neuroscience and neurobiology in the study of foreign policy and diplomacy, for example ( Hamati-Ataya, 2012 , p. 19). Obviously, these studies have not abandoned the dream of establishing a science very similar to the natural sciences nor did they give up on the value of an empirical understanding of reality.

Calls for a return to experimental research are on the rise because of technological and software advances that highly improve the results of this kind of research, even allowing for the emergence of new experimental approaches such as the multi-investigator experimental survey or the use of laboratory experiments to explore the impact of media, for example ( Druckman et al. , 2006 , p. 630).

Some even advocate the “end of theories,” meaning the decline in the need for explanatory models. They claim that the role of human beings in interpretation and analysis could be dispensed with. That role is now performed by the machine, which – relying on a huge amount of information; the big data – can make sound enough decisions on its own ( Moawad, 2020 , pp. 9–14). It is interesting to note how these calls maintain the same early behaviouralist tones of the value free science – only in a more modern language – where the role of researcher in the research process itself is reducible to that of a neutral observer, now even replaceable by an advanced computer.

Regardless of different assessments of the contemporary weight of behaviouralism, there is no doubt that behaviourialism has left a highly influential impact on the field of IR in its contemporary form. Even amongst the most informed academic circles, it still does not go without resistance to introduce studies in IR that are not based on testable observation. Cherishing the behaviouralist contribution to IR, Inanna ( Hamati-Ataya, 2012 , p. 20) wonders what the field would have looked like, if it had not been for behaviouralist insistence not to surrender:

[…] to the easier options of either asserting transcendental truths with no concern for their empirical accuracy or impact on human life, or of offering a loosely descriptive account of the world from an uncommon-sense, or introspective perspective.

Exactly because of this continued appreciation of a positivist understanding of the social world, the road ahead of post-positivist theories in the field of IR has not been that easy. The following section addresses some of the challenges facing post-positivist methodology and research methods in the field.

Overdue confession: positivism is not the only viable scientific methodology

The reconciliation between qualitative and quantitative research methods and the reconsideration of the possibility of formulating general theories in IR have only addressed some aspects of criticism directed at behaviouralism. In the corridors of the theory of IR, other aspects of criticism directed at behaviouralism were still lingering. Some theoretical developments would cast serious doubts about the positivist understanding of neutrality and objectivity, about the quality of the political analysis that ignores nonmaterial aspects such as ideas, values, interpretations and about the nature of political reality and its independent existence from researchers trying to understand it. It is these critical trends that would gradually draw attention to a metatheoretical relationship between neo-realism, neo-liberalism and Marxism, the theoretical trilogy that Rennger [quoted in ( Hamchi, 2011 , p. 214)] described as variations of “the same traditional Western epistemology and its methodological correlates – rationalism, positivism and pragmatism,” even though the three of them were supposed to be rivals.

By the late 1980s, calls would emerge to acknowledge an implicitly ongoing process of “(meta)theoretical restructuring of international relations theory” ( Neufeld, 1995 , p. 3), calls drawing attention to the emerging critical post-positivist theorizing.

“Post-positivism” is a quite ambiguous label. The term has been used at different stages of the development of the study of IR to describe different kinds of theoretical contributions. In the 1970s and 1980s, those dissatisfied with the behaviouralist obsession with a value-free science focusing mainly on the material aspects of the social world were sometimes referred to as post-positivists. This explains why the label “post-positivism” was granted to early contributions from the English school, social constructivism, feminism, etc. ( Reus-Smit , 2009a, 2009b , p. 66). Later, the label “post-positivism” will be more cautiously granted only to change seeking/reflexive/deconstructive, rather than problem-solving ( Eun, 2017 , pp. 593–607), contributions in the field, as a result of some growing awareness that a mere concern with values or other non-materialist aspects of the social phenomena is not a guarantee of a different mode of scientific theorizing – not a guarantee of a departure away from positivism ( Hamchi, 2011 ; Wiener, 2004 ).

Actually, it makes a lot of sense to claim that many of the theories that would fall today under the critical post-positivist category have a positivist version as well. This explains one classification of theories in the field that distinguishes between positivist critical theories and post-positivist critical theories ( Lamp, 2020 ). Feminism is different from critical feminism, and conventional or classical constructivism is different from interpretive/critical constructivism, even the critical theory itself has at least two generations ( Neufeld, 1993 ; Neufeld, 1995 ).

This is partly the reason why IR literature disagrees on how to label this mainstream-critical divide, whether to call it a third debate or a fourth debate ( Diez and Steans, 2005 , p. 127) to clearly distinguish it from a third debate that accepted theoretical plurality and opened up gradually not only to neo-liberal and neo-Marxist contributions but also to a feminist theory, a green theory, a constructivist theory, etc., a plurality that would, nonetheless, still be placeable under the umbrella of positivism.

Post-positivism departs from a complete set of alternative assumptions

First, theoretical reflexivity: theories are not just neutral descriptions of interactions between social actors (states, individuals, organizations, etc.). Whilst positivist theories develop hypotheses to be tested against reality ( Neufeld, 1990 , p. iii), post-positivist theories consider the “givens” of reality as non-given; as products of the theory itself, therefore, reality can never really become the judge of good theory ( Diez and Steans, 2005 , pp. 129–130).

Besides, how a researcher chooses his topics, how he selects his research methods and how he interprets or understands them is a derivative from his research preferences ( Ferguson and Mansbach, 2020 ), from his intellectual and political interests and from the historical setting that shapes his understanding of reality, i.e. his “historical circle” ( Diez and Steans, 2005 , p. 139). Bias is embedded in all theories regardless of how objective or neutral they claim to be. This is why realism is usually identified in this literature as an ideology that served the goals of establishing an international system with American hegemony after the end of the Second World War ( Ferguson and Mansbach, 2020 ). Knowledge can, therefore, only be understood within a context of time, space and interests ( Krauss, 2005 , p. 759).

Post-positivist theorizing warns against “self-fulfilling and self-defeating prophecies” that result from “people theorizing about the behaviour of people” ( Diez and Steans, 2005 , p. 141). Theories play a role in shaping the world which in turn is continuously reproduced in a way that reflects the understandings of the theories that seek to understand it. Leaders believing in realism will only see an international environment fraught with perils, they will most likely act according to a realist logic, even though they know of the existence of international cooperation or others, leading thereby to the fulfilling of realist prophecies about a world of anarchy and self-help ( Krauss, 2005 , p. 759).

Second, interpretivism: the post-positivist reflexive methodology conflicts with the logic of causation. It distinguishes between constitutive and causal relationships, taking pride in producing knowledge beyond what is observable, tangible, measurable and empirically testable ( Diez and Steans, 2005 , p. 141). No matter how similar behaviours appear to be, the difference in the real motives and the “uninterpreted facts” behind them necessarily makes them widely different from each other ( Ferguson and Mansbach, 2020 ). Therefore, quantitative and mathematical research tools for analysing international reality are far from sufficient, just in a way similar to the understanding of a language, where knowing the rules of grammar and the meaning of words is not enough for understanding what people say; the motives behind the words would make a true difference in meaning ( Diez and Steans, 2005 , p. 138).

Third, commitment to social change: post-positivist theorizing has a fundamental function of social criticism oriented toward emancipation, giving preference to change over stability and over the maintenance of the status quo by solving its problems ( Chernoff, 2007 , p. 131), believing in the creative role of human consciousness to guide the process of change ( Neufeld, 1990 , p. 3). The ability to subject one’s own assumptions to self-criticism is just an innate feature of post-positivist theorizing; continuously re-evaluating their commitment to change and emancipation, reassessing the extent to which their theorizing has managed to rid itself of Eurocentric, modern and positivist biases, thereby quite often producing new versions of the same theory at every stage. Though self-criticism is usually a point of strength, it sometimes seems to impede the ability of critical post-positivist theorizing to provide some stable, accumulated theoretical structures (Abou Samra, 2016, pp. 1409–1508).

Fourth, a commitment to plurality: post-positivist theorizing will draw the attention to the irony embedded in the dedication in non-Western peripheral academic circles to a consumption of the American positivist scientific project, inspite of its shortcomings in grasping the essence of non-Western reality or representing non-Western interests ( Jones, 2004 ).

Though post-positivist literature seriously acknowledges cultural diversity and its impact on the understanding of IR, it is important to note that the fourth debate remains a debate confined to theories competing within a secular world view. Even if the human mind is unable to explain all the aspect of political reality with reference to what is observable and empirically testable as post-positivists believe, the hidden part of the phenomenon remains produced – according to them – by social interactions ( Ekkehart Krippendorff, 1987 , pp. 29–30). “The emancipatory reference for critical theory is immanent to practices of the society itself, rather than an external, transcendental criterion for ethical judgement” ( Oliveira, 2018 , p. 9). Some reflection on alternative non-secular answers to questions of IR follows in the conclusion.

Post-positivism evaluated

The evaluation of the contribution of post-positivist theories to the field is quite controversial. Critics hold them responsible for turning the field into a field of “isolated theoretical islands” with no particular subject, characterized by fluidity in the absence of a clear-cut methodology ( Lamont, 2015 , p. 13), turning the field into a field where anything goes ( Ferguson and Mansbach, 2020 ). Critics accuse post-positivist theories of being unable to answer the most important questions in the field on how to explain war or how to maintain peace between states ( Neufeld, 1995 , pp. 330–331), even of being normative and detached from reality.

It is important to note that most of these criticisms depart basically from an inability to acknowledge the post-positivist methodology as a viable “scientific” methodology ( Ferguson and Mansbach, 2020 ). Obviously, many of the theorists – who accepted relatively easily some plurality of research methods, failed to welcome a plurality of methodology, even less a plurality of epistemologies ( Smith, 2000 , p. 375).

Post-positivism, in these criticisms, seems to be judged against the dictates of a methodology that it came to revolt against. Post-positivism is not there to better provide causal explanations of reality, it is there to better change reality.

In return, many cherish the fact that the post-positivist stage of the development of the study of IR has brought some serious novelty into the field at the level of approaches and research methods.

First, inspite of their diversity, post-positivist theories will appear to complement each other, rather than compete against each other ( Diez and Steans, 2005 ). This is not to be confused with the neo-neo consensus, acknowledged since the 1990s, for example ( Jackson and Sorenson, 2003 , p. 128), where neo-liberals and neo-realists, though having much in common, will remain competing against each other. Post-positivist theories are mutually reinforcing, their approaches are reciprocated and their concerns and aspirations for changing international reality are shared. That is why compound titles such as critical feminism, feminist post-colonialism, critical constructivism and deconstructive linguistic approaches are quite familiar ( Achilleos-Sarl, 2018 , pp. 34–46). Concepts such as emancipation, deconstruction and the power of knowledge are well known in post-positivist literature in a way that seems better representative of real plurality, where all theories are capable of complementing each other, whilst maintaining their unique characteristics and assumptions.

Second, post-positivist theories have developed, sometimes borrowed, some unique multi-levelled research approaches.

At one level, the assumptions of post-positivist theories themselves will serve as approaches to IR. It is quite common to encounter the terms feminist approach, post-colonial approach or poststructuralist approach ( Hesse-Biber and Leavy, 2006 , p. 105). Here, the mere elaboration of the post-positivist critical assumptions and the mere exposure of biases, both in theory and in reality, against the excluded, the weak and the marginalized in different social contexts become a research goal in itself ( Tickner, 2020 , p. 628).

At a second level, some specialized research methods were developed sharing the goal of making “the voices of the voiceless heard.” Here, critical post-positivist theories quite often rely on interdisciplinary approaches – approaches from the fields of philosophy, linguistics, literature, history, sociology and anthropology. These approaches are also quite often referred to as “qualitative research methods,” but they differ greatly from the positivist qualitative methods previously addressed. All post-positivist qualitative approaches share the assumption that reality is not independent of those who seek to understand it, and they work on revealing biases behind common sense understandings of reality. The ethnographic approach, focusing on everyday life and global processes, dealing with experiences as diverse as life in refugee camps and online shopping ( Windsor, 1989 , pp. 229–270), and the discourse analytic approach, focusing on the construction of realities through political discourse ( Jackson, 2007 , pp. 394–426) are some telling examples of such approaches.

At a third level, “metatheoretical approaches” emerged in the field, addressing the level of the metatheory of IR; the epistemological approach, with the Afrocentric feminist epistemological approach being an example ( Hesse-Biber and Leavy, 2006 , pp. 80–84), the constructive engagement approach, revealing cultural similarities at the level of philosophy ( Dottin, 2019 , pp. 40–41), are but examples of approaches revealing biases against non-mainstream epistemologies and contemplating on power relations existing at the levels of epistemology, ontology and methodology.

Post-positivism is, therefore, credited with a gradual expansion of the field of IR, theoretical and methodological expansion, disciplinary expansion – beyond IR and political science, substantive expansion and territorial expansion beyond the West ( Hellman, 2011 , p. 21).

An overview of the development of the study of the field reveals a complex interplay between theories, methodologies, research methods and reality. It is quite difficult to say whether the neo-realist relative failure – in the face of the end of the Cold War – caused the demise of the empiricist behaviouralist project or whether the failure of behaviouralism to grasp the aspects of the international phenomena left the neo-realist theory – and later on the neoliberal and neomarxist theories – with limited analytical resources in the face of a highly complex world in which poverty, climate change, religious resurgence, even epidemics seem to be not less dangerous to human existence than wars, free trade and the spread of capitalism – the issues of utmost priority to traditional IR theories. By the same logic it is quite difficult to say, whether the emergence of post-positivist research tools was the result of new developments in reality that were not understandable using positivist techniques, or whether the post-positivist tools have made us identify some aspects of reality to which we were completely insensible. For sure, post-positivist theorizing managed to expose some biases built into our understanding of IR; biases favouring the white, the male, the Western, the secular, the rich, the materially powerful, the rational, etc. ( Grosfoguel, 2007 , pp. 211–223). The interplay between reality on the one hand and theories, methods and methodologies in IR on the other hand is undeniable and quite complex.

Besides, although the narratives of the field prefer to tell the story of the triumph of realism over idealism, the triumph of behaviouralism over traditionalism and the triumph of American positivism over non-positivist alternatives, an overview of the methodological history of the field, in its first 60 years, showed that neither realism, nor behaviouralism, nor positivism have ever gone uncriticized in the field, not even in the 1960s or 1970s which used to be considered as the heydays of these scientific endeavours. In the past 40 years, these very same endeavours have been continuedly challenged in a way that further raised doubts about stories of “triumph,” at least stories of absolute triumph.

One conclusion, therefore, is that the field has never really surrendered to advocates of “the single scientific methodology” discourse. Throughout its development, calls for embracing theoretical plurality, methodic plurality, methodological plurality, epistemological plurality, etc., have been a recurring feature of IR.

It makes sense to claim that the field of IR has witnessed not only methodic plurality but also methodological plurality through the stages of its development. Different research methods and different methodologies – though sometimes highly critical of each other – seem to coexist in the field of IR to this day. Years of fierce theoretical debates just led to the de facto coexistence of behaviouralist, empirical, statistical, mathematical, qualitative and quantitative research methods on the one hand and post-positivist, reflexivist, deconstructivist and interpretivist research methods on the other, reflecting methodic plurality and methodological plurality. Nothing is sacred in IR; all theories, all methods and all methodologies have undergone a process of criticism, self-criticism and change. Drawing a map of the field’s methodologies and methods reveals necessarily its dynamism and its plurality.

The impact of the whole paradigmatic understanding of IR on methodologies and methods is sometimes subjected to serious criticism, because it restricts knowledge, making one unaware of a lot of things just because they fall outside the scope of concern of their adopted paradigm, hence, making researchers “method driven rather than problem driven” ( Hellman, 2011 ).

The need to sometimes cross the strict boundaries of theoretical frameworks has been acknowledged under different labels; analytic eclecticism proposed by Sil and Katzenstein is one of them, where a degree of interdisciplinarity and a degree of complementarity between different approaches of different theoretical traditions become highly cherished ( Sil and Katzenstein, 2010 , p. 417).

However, the rise of new theories and the rise of new research methods have not necessarily been accompanied by the rise of new methodologies. Positivism – in its methodological aspects – has been underlying much of the theories of IR, even those that present themselves as rivals such as neorealism, neoliberalism, some main strands of the English school or of constructivism.

More importantly, positivism – in its aspects as a secular theory to existence – remains the dominant underlying view of positivist and post-positivist theorizing in IR.

This paper has basically reflected on the interplay between methodology and methods as manifest in the Western course of development of IR theory. An emerging non-Western research course has been deliberately left out for future research. An “Islamic Civilizational Paradigm of IR” would clearly distinguish itself from positivism and post-positivism, calling, thereby, upon a methodology that combines reason and revelation and research methods that comfortably accept this duality ( Mostafa, 2016 ; Abou Samra, 2019 ). Attempts at developing a Chinese theory of IR – though strongly benefitting from a constructivist turn – would suggest the importance of making use of Chinese philosophical heritage ( Noesselt, 2012 ). A Chinese theory and an Islamic paradigm are just but examples of many emerging non-Western alternative theoretical understandings of IR reflecting cultural particularity. These reflections even furtherly suggest that a plurality of methodologies and methods can go far beyond the positivist and post-positivist understandings of a world making one wonder how different IR in the age of a truly “global IR” can look like ( Acharya and Buzan, 2017 , p. 7), a stage opening up slowly and somewhat hesitantly to diverse understandings of reality, history, life and existence from around the world.

Abou Samra , A. ( 2016 ), “ The concept of universalism in international relations: a comparative study of critical theories (Mafhoum Alalameya Fee Alelaqat Aldawleyah: Derasah fee Etegahat Naqdeyah Muqaranah) ”, in Mostafa , N.M. (Ed.), International Relations in a Changing World: Comparative Paradigms and Approaches (Alelaqat Adawleyah Fee Alam Mutaghayer: Manthourat we Madakhel Muqaranah) , The Civilization Centre for Studies and Researches , Cairo , pp. 1409 - 1508 .

Abou Samra , A. ( 2019 ), “ An Islamic paradigm in a new map of the field of IR (Manthour Hadari Islami Fee Khareetah Gadeedah Lehaql Alelaqat Aldawleyah) ”, The Journal of the Faculty of Economics and Political Science (Magalet Kolleyat Aliqtesad wa Aloloum Alseyaseyah) , Vol. 20 No. 3 .

Abul-Fadl , M.M. ( 1994 ), “ Contemporary social theory: Tawhidi projections ”, The American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences , Vol. 11 No. 3 .

Acharya , A. and Buzan , B. ( 2017 ), “ Why is there no non-Western IR theory? Ten years on ”, International Relations of the Asia-Pacific , Vol. 17 No. 3 .

Achilleos-Sarl , C. ( 2018 ), “ Reconceptualising foreign policy as gendered, sexualised and racialised: towards a postcolonial feminist foreign policy (analysis) ”, Journal of International Women's Studies , Vol. 19 No. 1 .

Badran , W. ( 2000 ), The Study of International Relations in Western Literature and the Project of International Relations in Islam (Derasat Alelaqat Aldawleyah Fee Aladabeyat Algharbeyah we Mashrou Alelaqat Aldawleyah fe Alislam)) , The Center for Political Research and Studies, Faculty of Economics and Political Science, Cairo University , Cairo , pp. 69 - 96 .

Boassen , C. ( 1991 ), “ Approaches to the study of international relations ”, In Search of Peace Research: Essays by Charles Boassen , Macmillan Academic and Professional , London .

Chernoff , F. ( 2007 ), Theory and Metatheory in International Relations: Concepts and Contending Accounts , Palgrave Macmillan , New York, NY .

Davis , R.G. ( 1965 ), “ A study of some behavioural approaches to international relations ”, Master Thesis, Political Science Department, The University of Wyoming .

Diez , T. and Steans , J. ( 2005 ), “ A useful dialogue? Habermas and international relations ”, Review of International Studies , Vol. 31 No. 1 .

Dolan , L.M. ( 2014 ), “ Three pluralisms: theories, methodologies, and levels of analysis in the study of world politics ”, Departmental Honors Projects 27 , available at: https://digitalcommons.hamline.edu/dhp/27

Dottin , P.A. ( 2019 ), “ Sino-African philosophy: a re-constructive engagement ”, Comparative Philosophy , Vol. 10 No. 1 .

Druckman , J.N. , Green , D.P. , Kuklinski , J.H. and Lupia , A. ( 2006 ), “ The growth and development of experimental research in political science ”, American Political Science Review , Vol. 100 No. 04 .

Dyer , H.C. and Mangasarian , L. ( 1989 ), “ Editors’ introduction ”, in Dyer , H.C. and Mangasarian , L. (Eds), The Study of International Relations: The State of the Art , Palgrave Macmillan in Association with Millenium Journal of International Studies , London .

Ekkehart Krippendorff , E. ( 1987 ), “ The dominance of American approaches in international relations ”, Millennium: Journal of International Studies , Vol. 16 , No. 2 , pp. 207 - 214 .

El-Hayagna , A.M.H. ( 2001 ), “ Level of analysis and research methods in the Arabic studies of international relations. Analytical study: 1966-1995 ”, Studies: Humanities and Social Sciences , Vol. 28 .

Eun , Y.-S. ( 2017 ), “ To what extent is post-positivism ‘practised’ in international relations? Evidence from China and the USA ”, International Political Science Review , Vol. 38 No. 5 .

Ferguson , Y. and Mansbach , R. ( 2020 ), “ Reflections on the ‘third debate’, the ‘third debate’ 25 years later, symposium, International Studies Association ”, available at: www.isanet.org/Publications/ISQ/Posts/ID/304/25-Years-after-The-Third-Debate-Two-pianissimo-bravos-for-IR-Theory (accessed 2019)

Ferguson , Y.H. and Mansbach , R.W. ( 1988 ), “ The elusive quest: theory and international politics ”, International Affairs , Vol. 64 No. 4, Autumn .

Finnegan , R. ( 1972 ), “ International relations: the disputed search for method ”, The Review of Politics , Vol. 34 No. 1 .

Forward , N. ( 1971 ), The Field of Nations: An Account of Some New Approaches to International Relations , Palgrave Macmillan , London and Basingstoke .

Grigsby , E. ( 2011 ), Analyzing Politics: An Introduction to Political Science , Cengage Learning .

Grosfoguel , R. ( 2007 ), “ The epistemic decolonial turn: beyond political-economy paradigms ”, Cultural Studies , Vol. 21 Nos 2/3 .

Hafner-Burton , E.M. , Haggard , S. and Lake , D.A. ( 2017 ), “ The behavioral revolution and international relations ”, International Organization , Vol. 71 .

Hamati-Ataya , I. ( 2012 ), “ Behavioralism ”, Oxford University Press , available at: www.academia.edu/593814/Behavioralism_in_Oxford_Research_Encyclopedia_of_International_Studies_OUP_ed._Ren%C3%A9e_Marlin-Bennett_2019_2012_

Hamchi , M. ( 2011 ), “ IR fourth debate: pluralistic or hegemonic? Limitations to bridging the gap ”, Algerian Review of Security and Development , Vol. 1 .

Hay , C. ( 2006 ), “ Political Ontology ”, in Goodin , R.E. and Tilly , C. (Eds), The Oxford Handbook of Contextual Political Analysis , available at: https://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/

Hellman , G. ( 2011 ), “ International relations as a field of study ”, in Badie , B. , Berg-Schlosser , D. and Morlino , L. (Eds), International Encyclopedia of Political Science , Sage Publication (The online version in abridged form is available at: www.sage-reference.com/view/intlpoliticalscience/n295.xml ).

Herakovic , J.M. ( 1983 ), “ The cultural roots of behaviourism ”, Master’s Thesis, Department of Psychology, The Graduate College, Western Michigan University .

Hesse-Biber , S.N. and Leavy , P. ( 2006 ), The Practice of Qualitative Research , Sage Publications , London and New Delhi .

Hoffman , M. ( 1989 ), “ Critical theory and the inter-paradigm debate ”, in Dyer , H.C. and Mangasarian , L. (Eds), The Study of International Relations: The State of the Art , Palgrave Macmillan in Association with Millennium Journal of International Studies , London .

Jackson , R. ( 2007 ), “ Constructing enemies: ‘Islamic terrorism’ in political and academic discourse ”, Government and Opposition , Vol. 42 No. 3 .

Jackson , R. and Sorenson , J. ( 2003 ), Introduction to International Relations: Theories and Approaches , Second ed . Oxford University Press , Oxford .

Jones , B.G. ( 2004 ), “ From Eurocentrism to epistemological internationalism: power, knowledge and objectivity in international relations ”, Cambridge, Theorizing Ontology, Annual Conference of the International Association for Critical Realism , University of Cambridge .

Kanfo , S. ( 2017 ), “ A methodological turn long overdue, or why it is time for critical scholars to cut their losses ”, in Dyvik , S.L. , Selby , J. and Wilkinson , R. (Eds), What’s the Point of International Relations , Routledge , London .

Kaplan , A. ( 1964 ), The Conduct of Inquiry: Methodology for Behavioral Science , Chandler Publishing Co , Scranton .

Krauss , S.E. ( 2005 ), “ Research paradigms and meaning making: a primer ”, The Qualitative Report , Vol. 10 No. 4 .

Lacatus , C. , Schade , D. and Yao , Y. ( 2015 ), “ Quo Vadis IR: method, methodology and innovation ”, Millennium: Journal of International Studies , Vol. 43 No. 3 .

Lamont , C. ( 2015 ), Research Method in International Relations , Sage Publications , London .

Lamp , N. ( 2020 ), “ Towards a critical theory of globalization ”, San Diego, 47th Annual Convention of the International Studies Association ( www.allacademic.com ) .

Linklater , A. ( 1986 ), “ Realism, Marxism and critical international theory ”, Review of International Studies , Vol. 12 No. 4 .

Little , R. ( 1991 ), “ International relations and the methological turn ”, Political Studies , Vol. 39 No. 3 , pp. 463 - 478 .

McCalla , R.B. ( 1996 ), “ NATO’s persistence after the cold war ”, International Organization , Vol. 50 No. 3 .

Mahoney , J. and Goertz , G. ( 2006 ), “ A tale of two cultures: contrasting quantitative and qualitative research ”, Political Analysis , Vol. 14 No. 3 .

Mintz , A. ( 2007 ), “ Behavioral IR as a subfield of international relations ”, International Studies Review , Vol. 9 No. 1 .

Moawad , A. ( 2020 ), “ The effect of big data on the theories of international relations (Ta’theer Albayanat Aldakhmah fee Nathareyat Al’elaqat Aldawleyah) ”, International Politics (Alseyasah Aldawleyah) Supplement , Vol. 219 No. 2020 .

Mosafa , N. ( 2010 ), “ The problematics of research and teaching in IR from a comparative civilizational perspective (Eshkaleyat Albahth wa Altadrees fee Elm Alelaqat Aldawleyah men Manthour Hadari Muqaran) ”, The Islamic Methodology (Almanhageyah Alislameyah) , The International Institute for Islamic Thought , Cairo , pp. 840 - 846 .

Mostafa , N.M. ( 2016 ), “ The development of IR science between the great debates and the dialectics of epistemics (Masar Elm Alelaqat Aldawleyah bayna Gedal Almanthourat Alkobra wa Ekhtelaf Alnamatheg Ama'refeyah) ”, in Mostafa , N. (Ed.), International Relations in a Changing World: Comparative Paradigms and Approaches (Alelaqat Aldawleyah fee Alam Mutaghayer: Manthourat we Madakhel Muqaranah) , The Civilization Centre for Studies and Researches , Cairo , pp. 57 - 70 .

Neufeld , M.A. ( 1990 ), “ Toward a restructuring of international relations theory ”, PhD Thesis, The Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research, Carleton University .

Neufeld , M.A. ( 1993 ), “ Interpretation and the ‘science’ of international relations ”, Review of International Studies , Vol. 19 No. 1 .

Neufeld , M.A. ( 1995 ), Toward a Restructuring of International Relations Theory , Cambridge University Press , Cambridge .

Noesselt , N. ( 2012 ), Is There a “Chinese School” of IR? , German Institute of Global and Area Studies .

Oliveira , G.C. ( 2018 ), “ Reconstructive methodology and critical international relations theory ”, Contexto Internacional , Vol. 40 No. 1 .

Reus-Smit , C. ( 2009a ), “ Constructivism and the English school ”, in Navari , C. (Ed.), Theorising International Society: English School Methods , Palgrave Macmillan , London .

Reus-Smit , C. ( 2009b ), “ On the distinction between positivist and post-positivist versions ”, in Navari , C. (Ed.), Theorising International Society: English School Methods , Palgrave Macmillan , London .

Sil , R. and Katzenstein , P.J. ( 2010 ), “ Analytic eclecticism in the study of world politics: reconfiguring problems and mechanisms across research traditions ”, Perspectives on Politics , Vol. 8 No. 2 , pp. 411 - 431 .

Smith , S. ( 1989 ), “ Paradigm dominance in international relations as a social science ”, in Dyer , H.C. and Mangasarian , L. (Eds), The Study of International Relations: The State of the Art , Palgrave Macmillan in association with Millenium Journal of International Studies .

Smith , S. ( 2000 ), “ The discipline if international relations: still and American social science? ”, British Journal of Politics and International Relations , Vol. 2 No. 3 .

Sprinz , D.F. and Wolinsky-Nahmias , Y. ( 2004 ), “ Introduction: methodology in international relations research ”, in Sprinz , D.F. and Wolinsky-Nahmias , Y. (Eds), Models, Numbers and Cases: Methods for Studying International Relations , The University of MI Press .

Tickner , A. ( 2020 ), “ Core, periphery and (neo)imperialist international relations ”, European Journal of International Relations , Vol. 19 No. 3 .

Waltz , K. ( 1979 ), Theory of International Politics , Addison Wesley , London .

Wiener , A. ( 2004 ), “ Contested compliance: interventions on the normative structure of world politics ”, European Journal of International Relations , Vol. 10 No. 2 , p. 191 .

Windsor , P. ( 1989 ), “ Foreward ”, in Dyer , H.C. and Mangasarian , L. (Eds), The Study of International Relations: The State of the Art , Palgrave Macmillan in Association with Millennium Journal of International Studies , London .

Further readings

Akinyoade , D. ( 2012 ), “ Ontology and epistemology for peace and conflict studies ”, International Conference on the Security Sector and Conflict Management in Nigeria (University of Ibadan, Nigeria), 14-16 August .

George , S. ( 1976 ), “ The reconciliation of the ‘classical’ and ‘scientific’ approaches to international relations ”, Millennium Journal of Scientific Studies , available at: https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/pdf/10.1177/03058298760050010301

Lapid , Y. ( 1989 ), “ The third debate: on the prospects of international theory in a post-positivist era ”, International Studies Quarterly , Vol. 33 No. 3 .

Lapid , Y. ( 2020 ), “ 25 years after the third debate: two (pianissimo) bravos for IR theory, the ‘third debate’ 25 years later symposium ”, available at: www.isanet.org/Publications/ISQ/Posts/ID/304/25-Years-after-The-Third-Debate-Two-pianissimo-bravos-for-IR-Theory ( accessed 2019 ).

Corresponding author

Related articles, we’re listening — tell us what you think, something didn’t work….

Report bugs here

All feedback is valuable

Please share your general feedback

Join us on our journey

Platform update page.

Visit emeraldpublishing.com/platformupdate to discover the latest news and updates

Questions & More Information

Answers to the most commonly asked questions here

International Relations & War MA

Our International Relations & War MA offers you the opportunity to study international relations in a multi-disciplinary department devoted to the study of all aspects of war. You will study this course online, meaning that you can access our high standard of teaching and expert staff from anywhere in the world without disrupting your personal and professional life.

Key benefits

  • An entirely web-delivered degree course.
  • Be part of a world-leading department, a vibrant research community and an international student body, drawn from a wide variety of academic and professional backgrounds.
  • Academically rigorous course on which lecturers provide close support and guidance.
  • You will develop the skills necessary for in-depth and critical analysis of international affairs and become familiar with the latest research.
  • Course materials include specially written content, images, videos, maps, intensively used discussion forums and full access to the resources of our library’s extensive electronic holdings.
  • Maximum flexibility for you: access content and respond to discussion postings in your own time for each study unit.
  • If your own circumstances (time commitments, visa, accommodation, etc.) allow, you may choose, for one term, to take one or two residential modules in our campus in London.
  • As with many of our graduates, this MA enables you to prepare for a career in sectors relating to international, security, and military affairs, or helps you upskill yourself for promotion or career change.

Metin

“ Learning from each other and getting knowledge from debates and dialogues creates the total package for a good start in reaching your personal and professional goals in life. And last but not least, I got the best friendships for a lifetime. ”

  • Course essentials
  • Entry requirements
  • Teaching & structure

Employability

Past students from this course have gone on to build careers in NGOs, civil services, NATO, the UN, media and publishing, finance and investment and teaching, as well as in the armed forces. A number of our students have had articles published in peer-reviewed journals and undertaken further academic research. Several students have gone on to complete a PhD, and one teaches part-time at King’s.

Curious to find out more? Access on-demand content including taster lectures and talks, and meet our current staff and students on our subject hub page .

  • Fees & Funding

Application closing date guidance

We encourage you to apply as early as possible so that there is sufficient time for your application to be assessed. We may need to request further information from you during the application process.

  • Our first application deadline is on 10 March 2024 (23:59 UK time)
  • The final application deadline is on 26 August 2024 (23:59 UK time).

After the first application deadline, if the programme becomes full before the final deadlines stated above, we will close the programme to further applications.

  • How to apply
  • Register your interest
  • Chat to a student
  • Order a prospectus

Related departments

  • Faculty of Social Science & Public Policy
  • School of Security Studies
  • Department of War Studies

research methods in war studies and international relations

Open days and events

Chat with current students and King's staff to find out about the courses we offer, life at King's and ask any questions you may have.

research methods in war studies and international relations

Sharing our expertise and insights on the war on Ukraine

Researchers and academics in our Faculty of Social Science & Public Policy are using their expertise to inform discussion and...

Explore more

research methods in war studies and international relations

Accommodation

Discover your accommodation options and explore our residences.

research methods in war studies and international relations

Connect with a King’s Advisor

Want to know more about studying at King's? We're here to help.

research methods in war studies and international relations

Learning in London

King's is right in the heart of the capital.

Research Methods in International Relations

Research methods in International Relations can be daunting to grasp, but put simply they are the tools and techniques used by students and academics to properly design research questions, and more importantly to reach persuasive and credible answers to those questions. The resources below outline the methods used in International Relations, starting from basic overviews and the levels of analysis, and then continue into more specific and detailed areas.

TopVectorElements/shutterstock

Different Methods and Approaches

EVorona/shutterstock

Please Consider Donating

Before you download your free e-book, please consider donating to support open access publishing.

E-IR is an independent non-profit publisher run by an all volunteer team. Your donations allow us to invest in new open access titles and pay our bandwidth bills to ensure we keep our existing titles free to view. Any amount, in any currency, is appreciated. Many thanks!

Donations are voluntary and not required to download the e-book - your link to download is below.

research methods in war studies and international relations

  • Subject List
  • Take a Tour
  • For Authors
  • Subscriber Services
  • Publications
  • African American Studies
  • African Studies
  • American Literature
  • Anthropology
  • Architecture Planning and Preservation
  • Art History
  • Atlantic History
  • Biblical Studies
  • British and Irish Literature
  • Childhood Studies
  • Chinese Studies
  • Cinema and Media Studies
  • Communication
  • Criminology
  • Environmental Science
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • International Law

International Relations

  • Islamic Studies
  • Jewish Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Latino Studies
  • Linguistics
  • Literary and Critical Theory
  • Medieval Studies
  • Military History
  • Political Science
  • Public Health
  • Renaissance and Reformation
  • Social Work
  • Urban Studies
  • Victorian Literature
  • Browse All Subjects

How to Subscribe

  • Free Trials

In This Article Expand or collapse the "in this article" section Process Tracing Methods

Introduction, debates about case studies and case-based methods.

  • Productive Account / Systems Approach to Studying Mechanisms
  • Minimalist Approach to Studying Mechanisms
  • Bayesian Approaches
  • Non-Bayesian Approaches
  • Case Selection and Combining Process Tracing with Other Methods
  • Comparative Politics
  • Environmental Politics
  • European Integration
  • Political Economy
  • Public Administration and Policy Studies
  • Examples from Non–social Science Fields

Related Articles Expand or collapse the "related articles" section about

About related articles close popup.

Lorem Ipsum Sit Dolor Amet

Vestibulum ante ipsum primis in faucibus orci luctus et ultrices posuere cubilia Curae; Aliquam ligula odio, euismod ut aliquam et, vestibulum nec risus. Nulla viverra, arcu et iaculis consequat, justo diam ornare tellus, semper ultrices tellus nunc eu tellus.

  • Experiments
  • The Empirical Testing of Formal Models

Other Subject Areas

Forthcoming articles expand or collapse the "forthcoming articles" section.

  • Crisis Bargaining
  • History of Brazilian Foreign Policy (1808 to 1945)
  • Indian Foreign Policy
  • Find more forthcoming articles...
  • Export Citations
  • Share This Facebook LinkedIn Twitter

Process Tracing Methods by Derek Beach LAST REVIEWED: 26 March 2020 LAST MODIFIED: 22 April 2020 DOI: 10.1093/obo/9780199743292-0227

Process tracing is an in-depth within-case study method used in the social sciences for tracing causal mechanisms and how they play out within an actual case. Process tracing can be used to build and test theories of processes that link causes and outcomes in a bounded population of causally similar cases, in combination with comparative methods, or, when used in a more pragmatic fashion, to gain a greater understanding of the causal dynamics that produced the outcome of a particular historical case. The strength of process tracing is that detailed knowledge is gained through the collection of within-case, mechanistic evidence about how causal processes work in real-world cases. Process tracing enables only within-case inferences to be made, making comparative methods necessary to enable inferences to causally similar cases. Comparisons make generalization possible because we can then claim that as a set of other cases are causally similar to the studied one, we should expect similar mechanisms to also be operative in these cases. Process tracing as a method can be broken down into three core components: theorization about causal mechanisms linking causes and outcomes, the development and analysis of the observable empirical manifestations of the operation of parts of theorized mechanisms, and the complementary use of comparative methods to enable generalizations of findings from single case studies to other causally similar cases.

To understand what process tracing is as a distinct case study method, it is important to have a good working knowledge of the underlying realist philosophical foundations of case-based methods. A wonderful and comprehensive introduction to different philosophical foundations of different social science methods can be found in Jackson 2016 . Good introductions to realist philosophy can be found in Maxwell 2012 and Sayer 2000 . It is also important to understand the core methodological debates about what case studies actually are. After the publication of Designing Social Inquiry ( King, et al. 1994 ), considerable debate has arisen about whether small-n methods, including case studies and small-n comparisons, constitute a distinct research approach or whether they can be subsumed under an overarching logic of studying variance. The “case-based” approach is articulated in Brady and Collier 2011 , George and Bennett 2005 , Goertz and Mahoney 2012 , Ragin 1987 , and Ragin 2000 , among others. This approach argues that small-n comparisons and within-case study methods, like process tracing, build on ontological and/or epistemological foundations different from “variance-based” approaches. The “variance-based” approach to case studies—including process tracing—is described in King, et al. 1994 and in Gerring 2017 . Here single cases are disaggregated into multiple “cases” in order to assess the difference that variance in values of a cause (or intervening variables) have for values on the outcome across units of the case.

Beach, Derek, and Rasmus Brun Pedersen. Causal Case Study Methods: Foundations and Guidelines for Comparing, Matching and Tracing . Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2019.

The book explores the foundational differences between case-based and variance-based approaches and develops a set of guidelines for using case-based comparative methods and process tracing.

Brady, Henry E., and David Collier, eds. Rethinking Social Inquiry: Diverse Tools, Shared Standards . 2d ed. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 2011.

Influential edited volume that explores different aspects of case-based research, including differences with variance-based approaches, and discussions of what types of evidence within-case analyses can use.

George, Alexander L., and Andrew Bennett. Case Studies and Theory Development in the Social Sciences . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005.

Influential book that developed core ideas about process tracing as a distinct research method, along with structured, focused comparisons and congruence case studies.

Gerring, John. Case Study Research . 2d ed. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2017.

Introduction to case study methods from a variance-based perspective.

Goertz, Gary, and James Mahoney. A Tale of Two Cultures: Qualitative and Quantitative Research in the Social Sciences . Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2012.

A very useful introduction to the core elements of case-based methods taken as a whole. Less helpful regarding how to use process tracing in practice.

Jackson, Patrick Thaddeus. The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations: Philosophy of Science and Its Implications for the Study of World Politics . 2d ed. London: Routledge, 2016.

DOI: 10.4324/9781315731360

Influential book that explores the foundational philosophical assumptions underlying social science methodologies, including neopositivism, (critical) realism, pragmaticism and analyticism, and reflexive approaches.

Johnson, R. Burke, Federica Russo, and Judith Schoonenboom. “Causation in Mixed Methods Research: The Meeting of Philosophy, Science, and Practice.” Journal of Mixed Methods Research 13.2 (2019): 143–162.

Useful overview article that discusses different understandings of causation, including a mechanistic account that is distinguished from counterfactual and regularity accounts.

King, Gary, Robert O. Keohane, and Sidney Verba. Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative Research . Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994.

DOI: 10.1515/9781400821211

Classic but controversial book that argues that cases should be disaggregated into multiple “cases” in order to investigate the difference that variance in the values of independent and intervening variables makes for the outcome.

Maxwell, Joseph A. A Realist Approach for Qualitative Research . Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE, 2012.

Great introduction to realist philosophy that develops an interpretivist epistemological stance while at the same time arguing for process understandings of causation as well as causal complexity.

Ragin, Charles C. The Comparative Method: Moving beyond Qualitative and Quantitative Strategies . Berkeley: University of California Press, 1987.

Classic book that develops some of the foundations for case-based methods.

Ragin, Charles C. Fuzzy-Set Social Science . Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000.

Book that introduces more advanced comparative techniques (qualitative comparative analysis [QCA]) within case-based methods. QCA is a useful tool in combination with within-case studies using process tracing.

Sayer, Andrew. Realism and Social Science . London: SAGE, 2000.

DOI: 10.4135/9781446218730

Concise introduction to critical realism that develops the distinctions between the real-actual-empirical, and that discusses the nature of causal mechanisms.

back to top

Users without a subscription are not able to see the full content on this page. Please subscribe or login .

Oxford Bibliographies Online is available by subscription and perpetual access to institutions. For more information or to contact an Oxford Sales Representative click here .

  • About International Relations »
  • Meet the Editorial Board »
  • Academic Theories of International Relations Since 1945
  • Al-Qaeda in the Islamic Maghreb
  • Arab-Israeli Wars
  • Arab-Israeli Wars, 1967-1973, The
  • Armed Conflicts/Violence against Civilians Data Sets
  • Arms Control
  • Asylum Policies
  • Audience Costs and the Credibility of Commitments
  • Authoritarian Regimes
  • Balance of Power Theory
  • Bargaining Theory of War
  • Brazilian Foreign Policy, The Politics of
  • Canadian Foreign Policy
  • Case Study Methods in International Relations
  • Casualties and Politics
  • Causation in International Relations
  • Central Europe
  • Challenge of Communism, The
  • China and Japan
  • China's Defense Policy
  • China’s Foreign Policy
  • Chinese Approaches to Strategy
  • Cities and International Relations
  • Civil Resistance
  • Civil Society in the European Union
  • Cold War, The
  • Colonialism
  • Comparative Foreign Policy Security Interests
  • Comparative Regionalism
  • Complex Systems Approaches to Global Politics
  • Conflict Behavior and the Prevention of War
  • Conflict Management
  • Conflict Management in the Middle East
  • Constructivism
  • Contemporary Shia–Sunni Sectarian Violence
  • Counterinsurgency
  • Countermeasures in International Law
  • Coups and Mutinies
  • Criminal Law, International
  • Critical Theory of International Relations
  • Cuban Missile Crisis, The
  • Cultural Diplomacy
  • Cyber Security
  • Cyber Warfare
  • Decision-Making, Poliheuristic Theory of
  • Demobilization, Post World War I
  • Democracies and World Order
  • Democracy and Conflict
  • Democracy in World Politics
  • Deterrence Theory
  • Development
  • Digital Diplomacy
  • Diplomacy, Gender and
  • Diplomacy, History of
  • Diplomacy in the ASEAN
  • Diplomacy, Public
  • Disaster Diplomacy
  • Diversionary Theory of War
  • Drone Warfare
  • Eastern Front (World War I)
  • Economic Coercion and Sanctions
  • Economics, International
  • Embedded Liberalism
  • Emerging Powers and BRICS
  • Empirical Testing of Formal Models
  • Energy and International Security
  • Environmental Peacebuilding
  • Epidemic Diseases and their Effects on History
  • Ethics and Morality in International Relations
  • Ethnicity in International Relations
  • European Migration Policy
  • European Security and Defense Policy, The
  • European Union as an International Actor
  • European Union, International Relations of the
  • Face-to-Face Diplomacy
  • Fascism, The Challenge of
  • Feminist Methodologies in International Relations
  • Feminist Security Studies
  • Food Security
  • Forecasting in International Relations
  • Foreign Aid and Assistance
  • Foreign Direct Investment
  • Foreign Policy Decision-Making
  • Foreign Policy of Non-democratic Regimes
  • Foreign Policy of Saudi Arabia
  • Foreign Policy, Theories of
  • French Empire, 20th-Century
  • From Club to Network Diplomacy
  • Future of NATO
  • Game Theory and Interstate Conflict
  • Gender and Terrorism
  • Genocide, Politicide, and Mass Atrocities Against Civilian...
  • Genocides, 20th Century
  • Geopolitics and Geostrategy
  • Germany in World War II
  • Global Citizenship
  • Global Civil Society
  • Global Constitutionalism
  • Global Environmental Politics
  • Global Ethic of Care
  • Global Governance
  • Global Justice, Western Perspectives
  • Globalization
  • Governance of the Arctic
  • Grand Strategy
  • Greater Middle East, The
  • Greek Crisis
  • Hague Conferences (1899, 1907)
  • Hierarchies in International Relations
  • History and International Relations
  • Human Nature in International Relations
  • Human Rights
  • Human Rights and Humanitarian Diplomacy
  • Human Rights, Feminism and
  • Human Rights Law
  • Human Security
  • Hybrid Warfare
  • Ideal Diplomat, The
  • Identity and Foreign Policy
  • Ideology, Values, and Foreign Policy
  • Illicit Trade and Smuggling
  • Imperialism
  • Indian Perspectives on International Relations, War, and C...
  • Indigenous Rights
  • Industrialization
  • Intelligence
  • Intelligence Oversight
  • Internal Displacement
  • International Conflict Settlements, The Durability of
  • International Criminal Court, The
  • International Economic Organizations (IMF and World Bank)
  • International Health Governance
  • International Justice, Theories of
  • International Law, Feminist Perspectives on
  • International Monetary Relations, History of
  • International Negotiation and Conflict Resolution
  • International Nongovernmental Organizations
  • International Norms for Cultural Preservation and Cooperat...
  • International Organizations
  • International Relations, Aesthetic Turn in
  • International Relations as a Social Science
  • International Relations, Practice Turn in
  • International Relations, Research Ethics in
  • International Relations Theory
  • International Security
  • International Society
  • International Society, Theorizing
  • International Support For Nonstate Armed Groups
  • Internet Law
  • Interstate Cooperation Theory and International Institutio...
  • Intervention and Use of Force
  • Interviews and Focus Groups
  • Iran, Politics and Foreign Policy
  • Iraq: Past and Present
  • Japanese Foreign Policy
  • Just War Theory
  • Kurdistan and Kurdish Politics
  • Law of the Sea
  • Laws of War
  • Leadership in International Affairs
  • Leadership Personality Characteristics and Foreign Policy
  • League of Nations
  • Lean Forward and Pull Back Options for US Grand Strategy
  • Mediation and Civil Wars
  • Mediation in International Conflicts
  • Mediation via International Organizations
  • Memory and World Politics
  • Mercantilism
  • Middle East, The Contemporary
  • Middle Powers and Regional Powers
  • Military Science
  • Minorities in the Middle East
  • Minority Rights
  • Morality in Foreign Policy
  • Multilateralism (1992–), Return to
  • National Liberation, International Law and Wars of
  • National Security Act of 1947, The
  • Nation-Building
  • Nations and Nationalism
  • NATO, Europe, and Russia: Security Issues and the Border R...
  • Natural Resources, Energy Politics, and Environmental Cons...
  • New Multilateralism in the Early 21st Century
  • Nonproliferation and Counterproliferation
  • Nonviolent Resistance Datasets
  • Normative Aspects of International Peacekeeping
  • Normative Power Beyond the Eurocentric Frame
  • Nuclear Proliferation
  • Peace Education in Post-Conflict Zones
  • Peace of Utrecht
  • Peacebuilding, Post-Conflict
  • Peacekeeping
  • Political Demography
  • Political Economy of National Security
  • Political Extremism in Sub-Saharan Africa
  • Political Learning and Socialization
  • Political Psychology
  • Politics and Islam in Turkey
  • Politics and Nationalism in Cyprus
  • Politics of Extraction: Theories and New Concepts for Crit...
  • Politics of Resilience
  • Popuism and Global Politics
  • Popular Culture and International Relations
  • Post-Civil War State
  • Post-Conflict and Transitional Justice
  • Post-Conflict Reconciliation in the Middle East and North ...
  • Power Transition Theory
  • Preventive War and Preemption
  • Prisoners, Treatment of
  • Private Military and Security Companies (PMSCs)
  • Process Tracing Methods
  • Pro-Government Militias
  • Proliferation
  • Prospect Theory in International Relations
  • Psychoanalysis in Global Politics and International Relati...
  • Psychology and Foreign Policy
  • Public Opinion and Foreign Policy
  • Public Opinion and the European Union
  • Quantum Social Science
  • Race and International Relations
  • Rebel Governance
  • Reconciliation
  • Reflexivity and International Relations
  • Religion and International Relations
  • Religiously Motivated Violence
  • Reputation in International Relations
  • Responsibility to Protect
  • Rising Powers in World Politics
  • Role Theory in International Relations
  • Russian Foreign Policy
  • Russian Revolutions and Civil War, 1917–1921
  • Sanctions in International Law
  • Science Diplomacy
  • Second Sino-Japanese War (1937-1945), The
  • Secrecy and Diplomacy
  • Securitization
  • Self-Determination
  • Shining Path
  • Sinophone and Japanese International Relations Theory
  • Small State Diplomacy
  • Social Scientific Theories of Imperialism
  • Sovereignty
  • Soviet Union in World War II
  • Space Strategy, Policy, and Power
  • Spatial Dependencies and International Mediation
  • State Theory in International Relations
  • Status in International Relations
  • Strategic Air Power
  • Strategic and Net Assessments
  • Sub-Saharan Africa, Conflict Formations in
  • Sustainable Development
  • Systems Theory
  • Teaching International Relations
  • Territorial Disputes
  • Terrorism and Poverty
  • Terrorism, Geography of
  • Terrorist Financing
  • Terrorist Group Strategies
  • The Changing Nature of Diplomacy
  • The Politics and Diplomacy of Neutrality
  • The Politics and Diplomacy of the First World War
  • The Queer in/of International Relations
  • the Twenty-First Century, Alliance Commitments in
  • The Vienna Conventions on Diplomatic and Consular Relation...
  • Theories of International Relations, Feminist
  • Theory, Chinese International Relations
  • Time Series Approaches to International Affairs
  • Transnational Actors
  • Transnational Law
  • Transnational Social Movements
  • Tribunals, War Crimes and
  • Trust and International Relations
  • UN Security Council
  • United Nations, The
  • United States and Asia, The
  • Uppsala Conflict Data Program
  • US and Africa
  • US–UK Special Relationship
  • Voluntary International Migration
  • War of the Spanish Succession (1701-1714)
  • Weapons of Mass Destruction
  • Western Balkans
  • Western Front (World War I)
  • Westphalia, Peace of (1648)
  • Women and Peacemaking Peacekeeping
  • World Economy 1919-1939
  • World Polity School
  • World War II Diplomacy and Political Relations
  • World-System Theory
  • Privacy Policy
  • Cookie Policy
  • Legal Notice
  • Accessibility

Powered by:

  • [66.249.64.20|185.39.149.46]
  • 185.39.149.46
  • Search Menu
  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Urban Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Language Acquisition
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Media
  • Music and Religion
  • Music and Culture
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Lifestyle, Home, and Garden
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Politics
  • Law and Society
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Medical Oncology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Medical Ethics
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business Ethics
  • Business Strategy
  • Business History
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and Government
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic History
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Political Theory
  • Politics and Law
  • Public Policy
  • Public Administration
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Developmental and Physical Disabilities Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

Oxford Handbook Topics in Politics

  • < Previous chapter
  • Next chapter >

Modern Deterrence Theory: Research Trends, Policy Debates, and Methodological Controversies

Department of Political Science, University of Missouri

Department of Political Science, University at Buffalo, SUNY

  • Published: 02 May 2016
  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

Modern deterrence theories were conceived in the aftermath of World War I. Given the human and political carnage associated with the Great War, it was natural for historians, military strategists, policy analysts, diplomats, and politicians to try to understand why the breakdown occurred. The standard interpretation of the coming of World War I provided the intellectual foundation for classical deterrence theory and its variants. This article traces these developments in the literature of war and conflict initiation and evaluates recent theoretical, empirical, and policy challenges to mainstream realist theory. It summarizes two synergistic variants of the classical specification of deterrence and contrasts them with competing explanatory frameworks, then examines the empirical literature on deterrence, recent theoretical developments in deterrence theory, and debates about deterrence policies. It concludes with a discussion of how the study of deterrence fits into the study of international conflict more broadly.

Although modern deterrence theories (there are more than one, and there are several variants) are generally traced back to the start of the Cold War period, they were actually conceived in the aftermath of World War I, a conflict that was brought about by the most massive failure of deterrence in the history of the international system ( Maurer 1995 ). 1 Given the human and political carnage associated with the Great War, as it was known at that time, it was quite natural for historians, military strategists, policy analysts, diplomats, and even politicians to try to understand why the breakdown occurred. Over time the accumulated understanding of its genesis provided the intellectual foundation for contemporary realist theories of the causes of war and, most important for our purposes, for classical deterrence theory. There is a straight theoretical line from Carr (1939) through Morgenthau (1948) to Brodie (1946 , 1959 ), Schelling (1960 , 1966 ), and Waltz (1979) that takes as its starting point “a specific interpretation of a single historical episode: the coming of the First World War during the July Crisis of 1914” ( Trachtenberg 1990/1991 , 76).

Our purpose in this article is not only to trace these developments in the literature of war and conflict initiation, but also to evaluate recent theoretical, empirical, and policy challenges to standard realist theory. We begin by summarizing two synergistic variants of the classical specification of deterrence theory and contrast them with competing explanatory frameworks, particularly perfect deterrence theory. After that we examine the empirical literature on deterrence, recent theoretical developments in deterrence theory, and debates about deterrence policies. We conclude with a discussion of how the study of deterrence fits into the study of international conflict more broadly.

Theories of Deterrence

If modern deterrence theories were born in the wake of World War I, they came of age as World War II was winding down. By that time, the contentious debate between liberal and realist thinkers was seemingly resolved ( Carr 1939 ). In short order, realist thinkers came to dominate strategic discourse in both academic and policy-making circles, and “power” emerged as the defining concept of the period (e.g., Morgenthau 1948 ). If Brodie (1946 , 76) was right that, after Hiroshima and Nagasaki, the chief purpose of military forces was not to win wars but to avert them, then skillful power management would be required. Almost to a theorist, realist thinkers saw a balance of power as the structural condition necessary for peace to prevail—that is, for deterrence to work. Indeed, at the dawn of the Cold War era, balance of power theory constituted the conventional wisdom of the field. Thus, it is more than understandable that the first wave of modern deterrence theorists ( Jervis 1979 ) took as axiomatic the pacifying nature of a strategic balance. According to former Soviet spymaster Pavel Sudoplatov (1994 , 195), some of the West’s leading scientists believed so strongly in the positive relationship between peace and a balance of (atomic) power that they passed sensitive information derived from the Manhattan Project to the Soviets: “Since [J. Robert] Oppenheimer, [Niels] Bohr and [Enrico] Fermi were fierce opponents of violence, they would seek to prevent a nuclear war, creating a balance of power, through sharing the secrets of atomic energy.” 2

Balance of power theory, however, was constructed on a weak empirical base ( Vasquez 1997 , 903). For instance, it is now well understood that World War I was waged under parity conditions, leading Kenneth Waltz (1993 , 77) to observe that “if … an ‘equality of power … among the major powers’ minimizes the likelihood of war, World War I should never have been fought.” Predictably, some modern deterrence theories were adjusted to take cognizance of this fact and a new variable, the cost of war, was called on to explain away the empirical anomaly. In consequence, two distinct, albeit synergistic, strands of realist theory were developed, each of which rested on what Gaddis (1986) called the “twin pillars” of deadly nuclear weapons and a carefully managed strategic balance: structural deterrence theory and decision-theoretic deterrence theory .

Structural deterrence theory focuses on the interplay between system structure and the cost of conflict to explain the absence of war during the Cold War period. By contrast, decision-theoretic deterrence theory explores the same question within a choice-theoretic framework. Together, these two strands of realist theory constitute what we refer to as classical deterrence theory, which is the dominant paradigmatic articulation of deterrence theory. 3

Structural deterrence theory is associated with two major propositions about the dynamics of deterrence:

Under parity conditions, the probability of war is monotonically related to the cost of warfare, or as Mearsheimer (1990 , 19) has put it, “the more horrible the prospects of war, the less likely it is to occur.” Thus, when the cost of war is, or is believed to be, low, war is possible. But as the costs of war increase, it becomes, ceteris paribus , less and less likely. And since in the nuclear age the cost of war is exorbitant, rational wars are all but impossible. Accidental wars, however, can always occur regardless of their cost.

By contrast, asymmetric distributions of power are associated with crises and war. When military capability, nuclear or otherwise, is unevenly distributed, deterrence is unlikely to succeed. Under these conditions either the weaker state will give in to blackmail (or as George [1993] would call it, “coercive diplomacy”) or the more powerful state will simply attack and enforce compliance to its demands. 4

Given these propositions, a number of policy recommendations follow. For example, most structural deterrence theorists oppose a policy of minimum deterrence; rather they argue for an overkill capability that raises the cost of war and, in their opinion, reduces its probability. For a similar reason they oppose both significant arms reduction agreements and comprehensive and effective missile defense systems. Logically consistent structural deterrence theorists also support the “selective” proliferation of nuclear weapons. 5 For example, some time ago Mearsheimer (1990 , 54) argued that a German nuclear capability was “the best hope for avoiding war in post-cold war Europe.” And more recently, Kenneth Waltz (2012) made the case that a nuclear Iran would enhance rather than detract from the stability of the Middle East.

Consideration of the cost of war seemingly enabled structural deterrence theorists to explain away empirical anomalies such as World Wars I and II, both of which occurred under parity conditions. Unfortunately, other discrepancies between theory and fact remain. To wit, unless they make ad hoc adjustments to their underlying theoretical construct, structural deterrence theorists are unable to explain why, early in the nuclear age, the United States did not attack the Soviet Union when it enjoyed, first, a monopoly on atomic weapons and, shortly thereafter, a clear-cut strategic advantage; why the Soviet Union did not exploit its preponderance over China when these two states were at loggerheads in the late 1960s and the early 1970s; or why, more generally, states have failed to jump through so-called windows of opportunity whenever they have existed ( Lebow 1984 ).

Given these empirical shortcomings, it should not be surprising that several competing structural theories of great power conflict have been developed. Of these, power transition theory ( Organski 1958 ) is the most well-developed. 6 And although Elman and Jensen (2014) categorize power transition theory as a realist theory, its underlying assumptions are starkly different than those of the dominant paradigm.

In the realist paradigm the international system resembles Hobbes’s state of nature; it is a self-help system without an overarching authority to enforce agreements. But where realist theorists see anarchy, power transition theorists see order. To be sure, the order is imposed—by a dominant power that is largely satisfied with the system it controls and benefits from. Such a system is seen as stable unless and until a dissatisfied challenger capable of contesting the status quo emerges. Clearly, for this condition to be satisfied, the challenger must have a reasonable chance of extracting concessions from the dominant state in an all-out conflict; that is, its power must approximate that of the dominant state. Parity, however, is seen as a necessary but not as a sufficient condition for great power wars (i.e., for deterrence failures). Peaceful power transitions are always possible. Nonetheless, ceteris paribus , war becomes more likely as the speed at which a rising challenger’s power base approaches that of the dominant state increases.

On its face, power transition theory is consistent with the fact that all major power wars since Napoleon’s time have been waged under parity conditions; it also explains the absence of war during the earliest stage of the Cold War ( Organski and Kugler 1980 ). Power transition theory, therefore, rests on a much firmer empirical foundation than structural deterrence theory. Nonetheless, as a theory of the necessary but not sufficient conditions of major power war, it leaves open a key question about the onset of war in the international system: Under what conditions will peaceful power transitions take place (i.e., when will deterrence succeed), and under what conditions will a peaceful transition fail to materialize (i.e., when will deterrence break down)? 7

It is clear that structural theories in isolation are unable to fully answer such fine grain questions; that is, that they are by nature largely indeterminate ( Keohane 1986 , 182–183). For specificity, a theoretical structure that takes account of human agency is required. Not surprisingly, classical deterrence theorists have also developed a strand of theory pitched at the individual level of analysis. Previously we have referred to this part of the deterrence landscape as decision-theoretic deterrence theory. And although this part of the literature includes work on deterrence that employs both expected utility theory and certain psychological choice frameworks, game-theoretic models have been dominant.

Decision-theoretic deterrence theory can be seen as a synergistic analogue to structural deterrence theory. Structural theorists conclude that in the nuclear age, in which the cost of war is exorbitant, rational wars are all but precluded. Decision-theoretic deterrence theory assumes the same. Unfortunately, as we show next, the seductive assumption that war is irrational leads to a logical inconsistency.

Consider Figure 1 , which is a simple extensive-form game model of a one-sided deterrence relationship. There are two players in this game, Challenger and Defender. Challenger, who by assumption makes the first move, has two choices: to cooperate or to defect from cooperation. Cooperation ends the game and results in the outcome called Status Quo ; defection brings about a subsequent choice by Defender. Should Challenger defect, Defender will have two choices (responses): to concede to Challenger’s demands, in which case the outcome is Challenger Wins , or to defy Challenger, in which case the outcome is Conflict (or war).

Rudimentary Asymmetric Deterrence Game (Defender’s Threat Is Not Credible)

The assumption that the cost of war is exorbitant is reflected in the players’ preference assignments, which are given as an ordered pair beneath each outcome in Figure 1 . The first entry in each pair denotes Challenger’s relative rank of that outcome; the second entry, Defender’s. The outcomes are ranked from best to worst, with each player’s most-preferred outcome assigned a “3,” its second most-preferred outcome a “2,” and its least-preferred outcome a “1.” Notice that the outcome called Conflict is the lowest-ranked outcome (i.e., 1) of both players.

The assumption that conflict is the worst outcome for both players is the defining assumption of decision-theoretic decision theory and is entirely consistent with the supposition that the cost of war in the nuclear age is prohibitive. Nonetheless, at the same time, it is inconsistent with the proposition that bilateral nuclear deterrence relationships are inordinately stable.

To see this, consider first Defender’s rational choice at node 2, which will only come about if and when Challenger defects at node 1. Since Challenger Wins is assumed to be Defender’s second most-preferred alternative, and Conflict is its least preferred, Defender—if it is rational—will choose to concede whenever it is faced with a choice at decision node 2. But if a rational Defender will concede at node 2, then a rational Challenger should defect at node 1. Should Challenger cooperate at node 1, its second most-preferred outcome, the Status Quo , results. By contrast, defection will bring about its most-preferred outcome, Challenger Wins . All of which is to say that the assumption that Conflict is a mutually worst outcome is inconsistent with the assumption that deterrence will succeed as long as the players are rational. Yet classical deterrence theorists, of either the structural or decision-theoretic persuasion, continue to contend that bilateral relationships between nuclear equals are inherently stable.

To resolve this, the paradox of deterrence, decision-theoretic deterrence theorists have offered a number of solutions, the most ingenious of which can be traced to the creative mind of Thomas Schelling (1960 , 1966 ). Perhaps Schelling’s most well-known, if not his most notorious, resolution of the paradox rests on Defender’s ability to convince Challenger that it is not rational, that it will execute a suicidal threat to retaliate despite the costs and despite its interests. If Defender is successful, then a rational Challenger will cooperate at node 1, since defection will only lead to its worst possible outcome.

But this tactic, which is sometimes referred to as the “rationality of irrationality,” fails to resolve the paradox; nor does it help to explain why the United States and the Soviet Union did not attack one another during the Cold War period. To understand why, assume for a moment that the United States is able to deter an attack by convincing the Soviet Union that it will—irrationally—retaliate. If this is the case, how then can one explain why the United States did not attack the Soviet Union? To say that US decision makers failed to upset the status quo to avoid the cost of nuclear war is simply another way of asserting that they were rational. Clearly any argument that simultaneously assumes that a player is rational when it is deterred, and irrational when it is deterring, lacks logical consistency.

Another suggestion, not only of Schelling but of numerous other decision-theoretic deterrence theorists as well, is for Defender to make an “irrevocable commitment” to retaliate. Such a commitment could be made in a number of ways. For example, in the run-up to World War I a British official asked Ferdinand Foch, the French general and military theorist, “What would you say was the smallest British military force that would be of any practical assistance to you in the event of a contest such as the one we are considering?” Foch replied, without hesitation, “One single private soldier, and we would take good care that he was killed” (quoted in MacMillan 2013 , 402). Foch was implying that the death of even one British soldier would force Britain to intervene on France’s behalf should Germany attack.

Schelling argued that US forces stationed in Europe during the Cold War served a similar function, that is, as a “tripwire” that committed the United States to defend its NATO allies. But as intuitively appealing as this argument is, as long as the assumption is that Conflict is a mutually worst outcome, it still requires an irrational choice by a player and therefore fails to satisfactorily resolve the paradox of deterrence.

Much the same can be said of Schelling’s (1960 , ch. 8) “threat-that-leaves-something-to-chance.” Underlying this tactic is the supposition that while it may be irrational for a player to execute a deterrent threat, it may be rational to threaten to unleash an “autonomous risk of war” outside of a player’s control. A challenger might be deterred, then, if the risk of an accidental or inadvertent war is unacceptable, that is, is high enough.

Unlike other suggestions to resolve the paradox of deterrence, Schelling’s “threat-that-leaves-something-to-chance” stands on firm logical ground. Powell (1987) proved this some time ago. Unfortunately, it is not the logical foundation of this potential resolution that fails to suffice; it is its empirical basis. To wit, there are no known examples of accidental conflicts ( Maxwell 1968 ), and that includes World War I. The idea that the belligerents simply “slithered” into World War I, to use David Lloyd George’s famous phrase, that it was an unintended conflict, has largely been discredited ( Lieber 2007 ; Trachtenberg 1990/1991 ; Zagare 2011 ). If there is anything that seems uncontested in the most recent scholarship on the Great War, it is the fact that it was brought about by human decisions ( MacMillan 2013 , 537). 8

Another way to think about the obvious disconnect between assumption and conclusion is in terms of the credibility of each player’s threat. In the strategic literature, credible threats are generally taken to be threats that are believable ( Smoke 1987 , 93). But threats can be believed only when they are rational to carry out ( Betts 1987 , 12); thus, only rational threats are considered to be credible ( Lebow 1981 , 15).

If a credible threat is a threat that is rational to carry out, then the assumption that Conflict is a mutually worst outcome is tantamount to an assumption that all deterrent threats lack credibility. The reason is straightforward. As demonstrated in the discussion of the game in Figure 1 , given the assumption that Defender prefers Challenger Wins to Conflict , its rational response at node 2 is to concede. And since it is irrational to execute the threat, it must perforce be unbelievable or incredible.

That deterrence should fail when a defender’s threat lacks credibility should be no surprise. What is surprising is that many who understand that threat credibility is all but necessary for deterrence to succeed also fail to recognize that the assumption that conflict is a mutually worst outcome eliminates the possibility that a player has a credible threat. In consequence, a logical inconsistency arises when players who, by assumption, do not have a rational or credible threat, are then assumed simultaneously to have one. This logical inconsistency is the basis of Achen’s (1987 , 92) insightful observation that “far from leaning too heavily on rational choice postulates, ‘rational deterrence theory’ necessarily assumes that nations are not always self-interestedly rational,” and of Brodie’s (1959 , 293) comment that “for the sake of deterrence before hostilities, the enemy must expect us to be vindictive and irrational if he attacks us.”

To eliminate the contradiction and resolve the paradox of deterrence, Zagare and Kilgour (2000) developed perfect deterrence theory. Unlike decision-theoretic deterrence theory, perfect deterrence theory makes no fixed assumption about the credibility of threats. Rather, it explores the logical implications of a variety of credibility states within the context of a number of closely related, incomplete information game models, the most austere of which is the Rudimentary Asymmetric Deterrence Game. One manifestation of this game is depicted in Figure 1 . Recall that in that game Defender prefers Challenger Wins to Conflict and that, therefore, it could not rationally execute its threat. If one also assumes that information is complete—that is, that Challenger knows Defender’s preferences for sure—then Defender’s threat completely lacks credibility.

Consider now the game in Figure 2 , in which the assumption is that Defender prefers Conflict to Challenger Wins . In this case, it would be rational for Defender to execute its threat and defy Challenger at node 2. And if Challenger knows this for certain, Defender’s threat would be completely credible. It is a straightforward exercise to demonstrate that deterrence will rationally succeed in the Rudimentary Asymmetric Deterrence Game when Defender’s threat is perfectly credible: given that Challenger knows that Defender will (rationally) defy at node 2, Challenger’s node 1 choice is to either cooperate and induce its second most-preferred outcome, the Status Quo , or to defect and induce its least-preferred outcome, Conflict . Clearly, a rational Challenger will choose to cooperate. All of which demonstrates that in the Rudimentary Asymmetric Deterrence Game, deterrence success depends on the credibility, or the lack thereof, of Defender’s threat.

Rudimentary Asymmetric Deterrence Game (Defender’s Threat Is Credible)

Perfect deterrence theory builds on this observation. But rather than assuming that credibility is fixed, it treats credibility as a variable. This is accomplished by assuming incomplete information. Specifically, Zagare and Kilgour assume that each player has probabilistic (rather than certain) knowledge of each other’s preferences. Each player’s credibility, therefore, is determined by the probability that the other believes that it prefers to execute its deterrent threat. 9 In other words, credibility is defined by the perceived rationality of a player’s threat to retaliate.

By relaxing the assumption that threat credibility is fixed and insisting that only rational threats can be executed, Zagare and Kilgour are able to develop an axiomatically distinct theory of deterrence pitched at the level of an individual decision maker. As a result it should be seen not only as distinct from, but also as a theoretical competitor to, decision-theoretic deterrence theory, much the same way that power transition theory stands in relation to structural deterrence theory. But perfect deterrence theory is distinguished from decision-theoretic deterrence theory in other ways as well; not only is its axiomatic base different, but its theoretical characteristics, its propositions about the dynamics of deterrence, and its policy prescriptions are also starkly at odds with those of its mainstream competitor. Table 1 summarizes these differences.

The most important difference concerns the two theories’ assumption about credibility. As noted, decision-theoretic deterrence theorists take credibility as a constant, yet they also assume, inconsistently, that irrational (or noncredible) threats can be executed. Perfect deterrence theory, by contrast, examines the strategic implications of a number of credibility states and insists that only credible threats will be carried out. In fact, perfect deterrence theory’s name derives from its strict adherence to Selten’s (1975) perfectness criterion, which is the basis of almost all solutions to extensive-form games and requires players to make rational choices at every decision node on a game tree. 10

While this difference might appear slight, it has significant empirical implications. Whereas the standard version of the theory concludes that high-cost parity relations are exceedingly stable, perfect deterrence theory finds the opposite. The two theories also differ on the implications of increasing the cost of conflict, either by augmenting the size of a strategic arsenal or by increasing its destructive potential. Nuclear realists like Waltz (1981) see a monotonic relationship between the cost of war and the probability of peace. Thus, since they claim that more is better, they support overkill capabilities that make war more expensive. And, as noted above, those classical deterrence theorists who understand the logical implications of their theories also support the selective dissemination of nuclear weapons (see, e.g., Mearsheimer 1990 , 1993 ; Posen 1993 ; Waltz 1981 ).

By contrast, in perfect deterrence theory, there is a distinct limit to the stabilizing effect of increases in the cost of conflict. Once that point has been reached, the probability of deterrence success does not increase. In consequence, perfect deterrence theory implies support of minimum deterrence policies that rest on a threat that is costly enough to deter an opponent, but that is not so costly as to render the threat itself incredible. In addition, the logic of perfect deterrence theory is inconsistent with policies that promote even the selective proliferation of weapons of mass destruction. 11

Rationality and Deterrence

In the previous section we briefly outlined two strands of classical deterrence theory: structural and decision-theoretic. We have also discussed two of its theoretical competitors: power transition theory and perfect deterrence theory. Thus, it is clear that there is more than one deterrence theory. Yet Morgan (2003) sees only a single theory. And on this score, Morgan is not alone. 12

One reason for Morgan’s view is a common thread that seemingly unites the several variants of modern deterrence theory: the rationality assumption. To be sure, the assumption is ubiquitous, which is one reason that the dominant paradigm is often referred to as rational deterrence theory. Nonetheless, there are important distinctions in the literature in the way this assumption is understood. These fine distinctions lead to very different theoretical structures and are the source of a great deal of pointless debate and criticism ( Zagare 1990 ; see also Quackenbush 2004 ). All of which is to say that “rationality” is an essentially contested concept ( MacIntyre 1973 ), that is, a concept that has no agreed upon definition.

Some theorists equate rationality with near omniscience. Verba’s definition is typical. According to Verba (1961 , 95), a rational actor is one who makes a “cool and clearheaded ends-means calculation” and considers all possible courses of action and carefully weighs the pros and cons of each of them before making a decision. Simon (1976) labels Verba’s and similar definitions of rationality procedural .

The demands of procedural rationality are severe. Clearly few, if any, real-world actors are procedurally rational. When critics of classical deterrence theory, such as Morgan (2003) or Lebow and Stein (1989) , dismiss classical deterrence theory because of this fact, they are most certainly correct. Nonetheless, the procedural definition can serve as a useful benchmark against which actual decisions can be evaluated. Decision-making pathologies and biases could not be recognized, or controlled for, unless this or a similar benchmark was used.

But there is another view of rationality that is commonly used by most formal theorists, including those whom we have labeled decision-theoretic deterrence theorists. According to Luce and Raiffa (1957 , 50), an instrumentally rational actor is one who, when confronted with “two alternatives which give rise to outcomes … will choose the one which yields the more preferred outcome.” Although this definition is less than demanding, it, too, serves a useful purpose. The assumption of instrumental rationality allows a connection to be made between a decision maker’s policy goals and its action choices. In the absence of this simplifying assumption, behavior is inexplicable, which is why Allison (1971) , perhaps unwittingly, uses it to explain state, organizational, and individual decision making during the Cuban missile crisis.

Parenthetically, it should be noted that Schelling’s “rationality of irrationality” stratagem plays on the distinction between procedural and instrumental rationality. What Schelling is saying is that it may benefit a player (i.e., it may be instrumentally rational) to appear to be procedurally irrational. By using two different definitions of rationality, Schelling introduces a logical inconsistency into his theoretical constructs and thereby renders them inscrutable.

To summarize briefly, there are two very different definitions of rational behavior that appear in the deterrence literature. Each serves a useful purpose. Specifications of deterrence that presume procedurally rational behavior, however, are obviously empirically suspect. By contrast, the assumption of instrumental rationality is a useful assumption precisely because it permits the derivation of hypotheses about the conditions associated with either deterrence success or its breakdown. But deterrence theories that merely assume instrumentally rational actors should not be rejected a priori. Rather, they should be judged by the accuracy of their propositions. When these propositions are supported empirically, the assumption of instrumental rationality has served its purpose.

Empirical Testing

While we have focused to this point on the development of deterrence theory, there has also been an extensive empirical literature on deterrence. Empirical studies are important for determining the extent to which deterrence theory helps to understand and explain reality ( Harvey 1998 ). The empirical deterrence literature has largely been divided between case studies and quantitative analyses. 13 A series of debates on case selection, the meaning of deterrence success, and the appropriate theory for testing is important for understanding much of this literature.

Selection of deterrence cases has been a subject of much disagreement, primarily between quantitative and case study researchers. An important symposium published in World Politics in 1989–1990 ( Achen and Snidal 1989 ; George and Smoke 1989 ; Huth and Russett 1990 ; Jervis 1989 ; Lebow and Stein 1989 , 1990) dealt in large part with the proper identification of immediate deterrence cases. However, selection of general deterrence cases has received much less attention. Quackenbush (2010 , 2011b ) argues that the difficult part of general deterrence case selection is not determining who makes deterrent threats (everyone does), but rather what states the threats are directed against. General deterrent threats are directed against any state that might consider an attack, so the key to general deterrence case selection is to identify which states might consider attacking which other states. He argues that the states that might consider an attack on a particular state are those that have the opportunity to fight one another, and uses politically active dyads ( Quackenbush 2006a ) to select cases of general deterrence.

Another concern that has often driven debates between those employing case study ( Lebow and Stein 1989 , 1990) and quantitative ( Huth and Russett 1990 ) methodologies is the determination of deterrence success or failure. However, game-theoretic models of deterrence do not make predictions regarding the success or failure of deterrence, per se; rather, the particular outcome of an interaction is predicted. 14 Furthermore, classification of certain cases as successful deterrence runs into a variety of conceptual and selection bias issues ( Danilovic 2001 ). Therefore, this issue does not pose a problem for empirical tests of game-theoretic models of deterrence. Non-game-theoretic theories of deterrence, however, should be expressed in terms of outcomes, rather than success or failure, in order to avoid this problem.

The third debate we consider here regards the appropriate theory for empirical analysis. The case study literature has focused on in-depth analyses of immediate deterrence in particular crises. These studies have generally not tried to test rational deterrence theory, but rather have criticized game-theoretic analyses of deterrence (e.g., George and Smoke 1974 ; Lebow 1981 , 1984 ; Jervis 1982/1983 ; Jervis, Lebow, and Stein 1985 ; Lebow and Stein 1990 ; Steinbruner 1976 ). Rather than seeking to test a theory of deterrence, they have sought to develop theory from case studies. This is of limited utility, not only because of difficulties of generalizing from a small number of cases, but also because focusing on immediate deterrence is subject to selection effects ( Fearon 2002 ).

The quantitative empirical literature on deterrence (e.g., Danilovic 2002 ; Huth and Russett 1984 , 1988 ; Huth 1988 ; Kugler 1984 ; Russett 1963 , 1967 ; Wu 1990 ) has examined the question of when deterrent threats work using large-N quantitative analysis. The focus of these studies has been almost exclusively on extended-immediate deterrence, with a few older studies (e.g., Huth and Russett 1993 ; Weede 1983 ) addressing general deterrence. Because of selection effects, the findings on when deterrent threats work in immediate deterrence may be misleading. As Fearon (2002 , 15) observes, “hypotheses that are valid for general deterrence should appear exactly reversed if we look at cases of immediate deterrence.” In addition, the quantitative literature has often tested individual hypotheses rather than testing any specific theory of deterrence. Signorino and Tarar (2006) provide an improvement over previous studies by conducting an empirical analysis of extended immediate deterrence using strategic probit, in which the empirical model is embedded within a game-theoretic model.

Quackenbush (2010 , 2011b ) argues that this has led to a divide between formal theories and the quantitative analysis of deterrence and endeavors to bridge the divide. He claims that the key to bridging the divide is to directly test theories of deterrence, and because of its logical consistency and explanatory power, perfect deterrence theory provides the best basis for testing. Quackenbush (2010 , 2011b ) tests the equilibrium outcome predictions of perfect deterrence theory. Since these predictions rely on the actors’ preferences, this requires explicit specification of utility functions for the actors involved. To do this, he employs a modification of the technique—using relative power as a measure for probability of victory and measuring utilities based on similarity of alliance portfolios—pioneered by Bueno de Mesquita and Lalman (1992) . Quackenbush uses binary and multinomial logit methods to examine the prediction of militarized interstate disputes and of particular game outcomes, and the results indicate that the predictions of perfect deterrence theory are generally supported by the empirical record.

Other empirical analyses have evaluated perfect deterrence theory as well. Danilovic (2002) evaluates perfect deterrence theory’s relationship predictions in her quantitative study of extended deterrence. She argues that a state’s inherent credibility—determined in large part by its regional interests—is a far more important predictor of deterrence outcomes than attempts to shore up credibility through the use of commitment strategies recommended by Schelling (1960 , 1966 ) and other classical deterrence theorists. Through her focus on credibility Danilovic (2002) directly addresses a key distinction between perfect and classical deterrence theories. As discussed above, the reason that classical deterrence theorists focus on commitment tactics as ways to shore up credibility is that they assume that all threats are inherently incredible. Zagare and Kilgour (2000) , on the other hand, argue that states’ threats are only credible to the extent that the state actually prefers conflict to backing down. Accordingly, Danilovic’s analysis is an attempt to determine what factors (relative power, regional interests, and democracy) lead states to prefer conflict over backing down.

Perfect deterrence theory has also been applied to the analysis of conflict settlements by Senese and Quackenbush (2003) . Their analysis demonstrates that perfect deterrence theory—through a comparison of the unilateral and generalized mutual deterrence games—makes predictions about the stability of different types of conflict settlements, and these predictions are strongly supported by the empirical record. This is an insight that was not gained through other analyses of the same subject.

Most attempts to test deterrence theory have utilized large-N, quantitative methods. Such analysis is useful because of the generalizable nature of conclusions derived from it. However, case studies would also be useful for future research. Since quantitative analyses demonstrate that perfect deterrence theory is generally supported by the historical record ( Quackenbush 2011a ), it should be no surprise to learn that there is also evidence that the theory can usefully be applied to particular cases. This can be done through the application of the insights of perfect deterrence theory to detailed case studies of particular historical episodes in order to understand these intrinsically interesting events more completely. For example, one study applies perfect deterrence theory to an analysis of the war in Kosovo to answer questions—such as why NATO’s threat of bombing was unable to deter Serbia, and later why Serbia escalated ethnic cleansing once the bombing started—to which others have struggled to find answers ( Quackenbush and Zagare 2006 ). Zagare (2011) tests perfect deterrence theory’s ability to explain the outbreak of World War I through an analytic narrative of the July 1914 crisis. He explains the course of the crisis by explaining a series of important decisions: the formation of the Austro-German alliance in 1879; Germany’s decision to provide Austria-Hungary with a blank check; why Russia, France, and Germany became involved in the dispute between Austria-Hungary and Serbia; and why Britain finally decided to enter the war. Furthermore, his analysis demonstrates that although general war was not sought by any of the actors, the war was no accident.

Theoretical Extensions

As we have seen, perfect deterrence theory is both logically consistent and empirically supported. Nonetheless, further questions regarding the dynamics of deterrence remain. Recent efforts to extend our understanding of deterrence have focused on four primary areas: three-actor games, bargaining, identifying credibility, and deterring terrorism and civil war.

Three-Actor Games

Although direct deterrence deals with two states, extended deterrence deals with a minimum of three. Werner (2000 , 721) outlines the basic logic of extended deterrence: “The attacker must decide whether or not to attack the target, which then must decide whether or not to resist. After observing both the attacker’s and the target’s actions, the third party must decide whether or not to come to the aid of the target if the target has in fact been attacked.” However, standard practice has been to include only two players in models of extended deterrence: the attacker (or challenger) and the defender. Indeed, virtually all analyses of extended deterrence have focused on only two players (e.g., Danilovic 2002 ; Huth 1988 ; Kilgour and Zagare 1994 ; Russett 1963 ; Signorino and Tarar 2006 ; Werner 2000 ; Zagare and Kilgour 1993 ). Thus, although Werner clearly highlights the presence and the choices of the target (as do others), the target’s role in the strategic calculation involved is generally ignored.

Therefore, an important development in deterrence theory has been to explicitly model deterrence situations wherein the choices of the target are strategically salient. Zagare and Kilgour (2003) do so through a Tripartite Crisis Game, which focuses on Protégé’s potential to realign with a more reliable partner should Defender not support her following a challenge. This highlights the importance of the “deterrence versus restraint” dilemma in extended deterrence, wherein Defender has competing interests in having a strong enough commitment to support Protégé so as to deter Challenger, but not in making such a strong commitment that Protégé would be encouraged to act recklessly.

Zagare and Kilgour (2006) extend this analysis to explain British policy in the July crisis leading to the outbreak of World War I. They demonstrate why halfhearted, extended deterrent signals are so often observed in international politics in general, and in Britain’s attempts to deter Germany in 1914 in particular. In so doing, they show that their analysis more fully captures the dynamics of the deterrence versus restraint dilemma than Crawford’s (2003) model of “pivotal deterrence,” which unfortunately is not based on the axiomatic base of perfect deterrence theory.

Quackenbush (2006b) also extends deterrence theory to consider the strategic interactions of all three actors in extended deterrence. He develops a Three-Party Extended Deterrence Game, a formal model that matches the basic informal logic of extended deterrence. This model is the first to explicitly model the simultaneous conduct of extended and direct deterrence identified by Snyder (1961) . Furthermore, the inclusion of all three players in the analysis allows examination of other issues such as the target of a challenge and of alliance reliability.

Quackenbush’s (2006b) analysis indicates that potential challengers look to attack members of unreliable alliances. Furthermore, deterrence is more likely to succeed the more highly Defender and Protégé value a war (bilateral or multilateral) with Challenger, and the less highly they value a concession to Challenger. In addition, Challenger’s increasing utility for the status quo also increases the probability of successful deterrence. And finally, when deterrence fails, the likely target of an attack by Challenger is the more reliable of the allies—in order to keep the unreliable side on the sidelines and prevent a multilateral war.

By including all three actors within game-theoretic models, these studies have significantly improved our understanding of the dynamics of extended deterrence. Certainly further developments in three-actor models are warranted, and they are being developed (e.g., Corbetta 2010 ; Langlois 2012 ; Yuen 2009 ). As Quackenbush (2006b) demonstrates, standard two-party extended deterrence games rely on the often hidden assumption that states always respond to direct challenges. But since this assumption directly contradicts theories of direct deterrence, analyzing all three actors in extended deterrence appears to be a more consistent way of approaching the problem.

Bargaining and Deterrence

Traditional analyses of international relations have modeled decisions as stark choices between two, or sometimes three, alternatives. This is illustrated in the Rudimentary Asymmetric Deterrence Game shown in Figure 2 , which presents choices between “Cooperate” and “Defect” or “Concede” and “Deny.” However, states often have a wide variety of options available to them; for example, rather than just choosing between “attack” or “not attack,” a state could do nothing, partially mobilize troops, fully mobilize, embark on a show of force, launch airstrikes, or even initiate a full-on invasion. This of course provides a much more nuanced menu of options than traditional models would suggest.

The bargaining model of war has been a recent focus of research on international relations (e.g., Fearon 1995 ; Slantchev 2003 ; Wagner 2000 ). Although models vary, they incorporate these nuanced options within the game-theoretic model, making the stakes under consideration endogenous to the model itself. Thus, states choose not only whether to make a demand, attack, and so forth, but also how much to demand, attack, and so forth.

Werner (2000) developed the first model of deterrence to incorporate these endogenous stakes. In her Modified Extended Deterrence Game, the attacker can choose the magnitude of the threat. By modeling the stakes of war as endogenous in this way, Werner is able to identify circumstances under which extended deterrence fails because the attacker deters the third party from intervening.

Langlois and Langlois (2006a , 2006b ) have also examined the relationship between bargaining and deterrence in analyses of direct, asymmetric deterrence. This allows the rivals to bargain over the terms of an alternative status quo. It also shows how war can erupt between two rational states even when there is complete information, contrary to traditional arguments. Similarly, Slantchev (2011) examines how military threats can be employed in the pursuit of political objectives. He focuses on how military threats can establish commitments and communicate intent.

Further analyses integrating such bargaining models within studies of deterrence are likely to continue to be a fruitful avenue for research. Nonetheless, it seems important to recognize the importance of domestic politics and its influence on the demands that states make. For example, Bueno de Mesquita and Lalman (1992) focus on two variants of their International Interaction Game: in the Realpolitik variant, the magnitude of the demand is purely endogenous to the game, whereas in the Domestic variant, the magnitude of the demand is assumed to be determined by domestic political processes and is thus exogenous to the game. Furthermore, they find that the Domestic variant does a much better job of explaining international interactions than the Realpolitik variant.

Identifying Credibility

A third important focus of recent theoretical developments has been on identifying credibility. Perfect deterrence theory demonstrates that credibility is an important determinant of deterrence success. In the presence of complete information, a state’s credibility is simply its preference between fighting and backing down; a state either has a credible threat (i.e., prefers conflict) or does not (i.e., prefers backing down). However, states seldom possess complete information about their opponents.

When there is incomplete information and a state’s preference between fighting and backing down is not known to its opponent, the situation is more complicated. In this case, a state’s credibility is the opponent’s estimate of the probability that it prefers fighting to backing down; thus, credibility varies continuously between 0 and 1 ( Zagare and Kilgour 2000 ). Forming accurate estimates of the opponent’s credibility is complicated by the reality that states have incentives to misrepresent their private information ( Fearon 1995 ). States have incentives to claim that they prefer to fight rather than back down regardless of their actual preference. How can states credibly communicate their commitment to fight in the face of these difficulties?

Two studies in particular have sought to address this question. Sartori (2005) develops a reputational theory of diplomacy whereby defenders acquire reputations for honesty or bluffing depending on whether or not they carry through on their threats to defend against the challenger. She finds that a defender’s reputation for honesty enhances its threat credibility and therefore increases the likelihood of successful deterrence; on the other hand, a reputation for bluffing undermines threat credibility.

In contrast, Press (2004 , 2005 ) proposes a “current calculus” model, which evaluates credibility based on the balance of power and interests at stake and argues that it does a better job of gauging states’ perceptions of their opponents’ credibility than the “past actions” model, which argues that credibility depends on one’s record for keeping or breaking commitments. His focus on assessing the interests at stake to determine credibility is quite reasonable given that credibility deals with a state’s preference between backing down and conflict.

However, it is important to distinguish between credibility and capability; whereas capability is a necessary condition for deterrence success, credibility is not ( Zagare and Kilgour 2000 ). But assessments of the balance of power appear to have more to do with a state’s preference between conflict and the status quo than with a state’s preference between conflict and backing down. Therefore, it appears that Press conflates credibility and capability. For example, he argues that Britain’s threat to defend Poland in 1939 was not credible, in large part because Germany (especially Hitler) misjudged the balance of power. It seems clear that, although it could not be certain, Germany believed that British intervention was likely, and thus the British threat was credible. But as Weinberg (1995 , 91) states, “in August 1939 Hitler preferred to attack Poland as a preliminary to attacking France and England, but he was quite willing to face war with the Western Powers earlier if that was their choice.” In other words, Germany preferred conflict with France and Britain to the status quo; despite being credible, the British threat was not capable.

Deterring Terrorism and Civil War

The final theoretical extensions we consider here focus on how states can deter terrorism and civil war. Civil war (e.g., Collier and Hoeffler 2004 ; Fearon and Laitin 2003 ) and terrorism ( Li 2005 ; Pape 2003 ) have been increasingly prominent topics of study in international relations in recent years. Although less attention has been paid to whether these groups can be deterred, and if so, how deterrence works in this context, studies on both topics are emerging.

Terrorism has been an increasingly popular tactic used by various groups around the world. Most famously, the attacks by Al Qaeda against the World Trade Center and other targets within the United States on September 11, 2001, led many to question why the United States was unable to deter Al Qaeda. More generally, people have questioned whether terrorists can be deterred at all. Trager and Zagorcheva (2005/2006) and Lebovic (2007) examine this issue and conclude that terrorists can be deterred. However, these studies fail to account for both the credibility and the capability of the deterring state’s threat. It would seem that whether or not a terrorist group can be deterred depends on its type. While some terrorist groups certainly can be deterred, others cannot, because they prefer to fight rather than stick with the status quo ( Kang and Kugler 2012 ).

There has also been some attention paid to deterring civil wars. Most prominently, Machain, Morgan, and Regan (2011) have developed a game-theoretic model to examine how states can deter rebel groups from engaging in violence. In doing so, they focus not only on the credibility of the state’s threat to retaliate against rebel attacks, but also on the credibility of its promise to refrain from punishment of groups that do not engage in violence. They show that proportionate retaliation directed only at actual rebels is the most likely to succeed. In contrast, state policies that focus on swift, severe, and disproportionate retaliations are more likely to fail.

Civil war and terrorism are two of the primary threats to international security in the modern age. Analyzing governments’ ability to deter domestic and international rebel groups is an important and natural extension of deterrence theory. Although work in this area is in its very early stages, we are hopeful that continuing studies will improve our understanding not only of government responses to civil war and terrorism, but also of deterrence more broadly.

Policy Debates

There have been a number of debates regarding deterrence policy over the years. A comprehensive review of this large literature on policy debates is beyond the scope of this article. Nonetheless, it is important to address the implications of our examination of deterrence theory and empirical studies for policy. The absence of logical consistency in classical deterrence theory has led to many conflicting prescriptions in the policy literature. Policy recommendations that flow from political imperatives rather than from strategic principles and a consistent axiomatic base are bound to contradict one another. Perfect deterrence theory, by contrast, offers a consistent perspective from which to view the dynamics of deterrence and a clear logic supporting its policy prescriptions. This is, perhaps, its most important feature.

Zagare (2004) and Quackenbush (2011a) provide more complete reviews of perfect deterrence theory’s policy implications regarding topics such as overkill capability, minimum deterrence, proliferation, and missile defense. We review some of the major themes here, focusing on differences in policy conclusions between perfect and classical deterrence theories.

As discussed previously, classical deterrence theory supports both an overkill capability (e.g., Intriligator and Brito, 1984 ) and the selective proliferation of nuclear weapons (e.g., Mearsheimer 1990 ; Waltz 1981 ; and Van Evera 1990/1991 ). Perfect deterrence theory opposes these policies. The logic of perfect deterrence theory demonstrates that there are distinct limits to the stabilizing impact of weapons of mass destruction and that an overkill capability, recommended by many classical deterrence theorists, is just that, overkill ( Zagare and Kilgour 2000 ).

Furthermore, classical deterrence theory opposes both minimum deterrence deployments and significant arms reductions. Perfect deterrence theory is consistent with both these policies. In both classical deterrence theory and perfect deterrence theory, the costs associated with conflict have significant strategic implications. But there are important differences in the conclusions the two theoretical frameworks reach about the impact of increased costs on the likelihood of deterrence success. Classical deterrence theory concludes that deterrence success becomes more and more likely as these costs increase. One reason for this straightforward connection between cost and stability is that most classical deterrence theorists assume fixed preferences: players always prefer an advantage to the status quo, and they always prefer not to execute their deterrent threat (i.e., threats are always incredible). Thus, any increase in the cost of conflict always has the same impact relative to other outcomes.

In perfect deterrence theory, by contrast, the cost of conflict is gauged against two other important strategic variables. The first is the value of the status quo ( Zagare 2004 , 127–128). One consequence of this variable relationship is that, in perfect deterrence theory, there is a minimum cost threshold below which deterrence cannot succeed. This is the point separating threats that are capable from those that are not.

The second reference point is the value of concession. In perfect deterrence theory, the players may, or may not, prefer to concede rather than execute a deterrent threat. This is the reason that there is also a maximum threshold beyond which further increases in the cost of conflict do not contribute to the probability of direct deterrence success. Rather than an overkill capability, then, the logic of perfect deterrence theory is consistent with a policy of minimum deterrence, which rests on a threat that is costly enough to deter an opponent but is not so costly that the threat itself is rendered incredible.

An equally important difference is that there is no simple monotonic relationship in perfect deterrence theory between the cost of conflict and the stability of the status quo, as there is in classical deterrence theory. In perfect deterrence theory, there are circumstances under which an increase in conflict costs will actually undermine a deterrence relationship. More specifically, extended deterrence becomes more and more difficult to maintain as conflict costs rise, simply because defenders become more and more reluctant to respond to an indirect challenge. In perfect deterrence theory, therefore, increased conflict costs can, under some circumstances, be stabilizing, but under others, may have the opposite consequence.

Finally, classical deterrence theorists prescribe coercive bargaining stances based on increasing war costs and inflexible or reckless bargaining tactics. By contrast, perfect deterrence theory suggests that conditionally cooperative policies based on reciprocity are more efficacious. Classical deterrence theory and perfect deterrence theory also differ about negotiating stances and the best way to conduct diplomacy. Recall that decision-theoretic deterrence theorists proffer coercive bargaining tactics that either reduce flexibility or increase an opponent’s conflict costs in order to increase the probability of an opponent’s concession. By contrast, perfect deterrence theory recommends an approach rooted in reciprocity. Conditionally cooperative strategies like “tit-for-tat” that reciprocate both cooperation and noncooperation are associated, both theoretically and empirically, with successful compromise.

In perfect deterrence theory, establishing reciprocity is tantamount to establishing credibility, which in turn makes deterrence more likely. Thus, it is reassuring that in Huth’s (1988) statistical analysis of extended deterrence relationships, firm-but-flexible negotiating styles and tit-for-tat deployments are highly correlated with extended deterrence success. Huth defines a firm-but-flexible diplomatic stance as a signal that the defender is willing to compromise, but not to capitulate. And a tit-for-tat policy involves an actual response in kind during a crisis or mobilization. Thus, the essence of both a firm-but-flexible bargaining approach and a tit-for-tat response to an actual provocation is reciprocity, the norm that signals credibility when promised or threatened and demonstrates it when practiced. There is, as well, a large empirical literature that is consistent not only with Huth’s findings but also with the theoretical expectations of perfect deterrence theory about the pervasiveness of reciprocal behavior in interstate interactions. This evidence attests to perfect deterrence theory’s explanatory and predictive power. By contrast, this widely observed norm is difficult, if not impossible, for classical deterrence theorists to explain.

Conclusions

Thirty years ago philosopher Anthony Kenny (1985 , ix) asserted that deterrence was “the key concept for the understanding of the strategy and diplomacy of the age.” Obviously, much has transpired since Kenny made his claim. The end of the Cold War was followed by conflicts in the 1990s in Iraq, the former Yugoslavia, between India and Pakistan, and elsewhere. Further, the 9/11 terrorist attacks ushered in a new “global war on terror,” as the United States and allies toppled regimes and fought counterinsurgency campaigns in Afghanistan and Iraq. The second decade of the twenty-first century witnessed civil wars and conflict in Libya, Syria, Ukraine, and elsewhere.

As these events unfolded, the significance of deterrence, as both a concept and a policy, came under intense attack. As a concept it was seen as largely irrelevant to the post–Cold War era, or, as Colin Gray (2003 , vi) put it, deterrence appeared to be in “semiretirement.” And as a policy, it was judged “obsolete” ( Krauthammer 2002 ). Many strategic thinkers concluded that deterrence was an ineffectual strategem against terrorists and other “undeterrables” ( Friedman 2002 ). Deterrence was also thought to be an inappropriate policy toward risk takers like Saddam Hussein, who operate in a world of half-truths, distorted intelligence, and incomplete information ( Pollack 2002 ). In Washington, the strategic doctrine of “preemption” was all the rage. To all the world it appeared that deterrence, like God in the 1960s, was probably dead. At a minimum, it was seen to be on life support. The situation appeared so bleak that the New York Times (2002) felt compelled to write an editorial “in defense of deterrence.”

But the news of deterrence’s demise was premature. Judging from the academic literature, this would certainly appear to be the case. Books and articles about deterrence continue to be published by the best academic presses and the major security studies journals. Among the significant book-length manuscripts on deterrence that have appeared since the turn of the century are Crawford (2003) ; Danilovic (2002) ; Freedman (2004) ; Gray (2003) ; Morgan (2003) ; Paul, Morgan, and Wirtz (2009) ; Payne (2001) ; Quackenbush (2011b) ; Sartori (2005) ; and Zagare (2011) . Taken as a unit, these works demonstrate that the core debates about deterrence’s theoretical underpinnings, its empirical robustness, its conceptual clarity, and its policy relevance continue.

All of which is to say that deterrence, and the theories that seek to understand it, stand at the very center of the discipline of international politics. Thus, it should not be surprising at all that despite suggestions to the contrary, research on deterrence is thriving, or that this scholarship is unlikely to go away now or in the foreseeable future. Our analyses of logic and evidence show that perfect deterrence theory provides the best available explanation of deterrence. Given its logical inconsistency and empirical inaccuracy, classical deterrence theory should be set aside. In our opinion, future theoretical developments, empirical analysis, and policy assessments are better served by using perfect deterrence theory as their foundation.

Achen, Christopher H.   1987 . “A Darwinian View of Deterrence.” In Exploring the Stability of Deterrence , edited by Jacek Kugler and Frank C. Zagare , 91–105. Denver, CO: Lynne Rienner.

Google Scholar

Google Preview

Achen, Christopher H. , and Duncan Snidal . 1989 . “ Rational Deterrence Theory and Comparative Case Studies. ” World Politics 41 (2): 143–169.

Allison, Graham T.   1971 . Essence of Decision: Explaining the Cuban Missile Crisis . Boston: Little, Brown.

Betts, Richard K.   1987 . Nuclear Blackmail and Nuclear Balance . Washington, DC: Brookings.

Brodie, Bernard , ed. 1946 . The Absolute Weapon: Atomic Power and World Order . New York: Harcourt, Brace.

Brodie, Bernard . 1959 . Strategy in the Missile Age . Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Bueno de Mesquita, Bruce , and David Lalman . 1992 . War and Reason: Domestic and International Imperatives . New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Carr, Edward Hallett . 1939 . The Twenty Years’ Crisis: 1919–1939 . New York: Harper & Row.

Clark, Christopher . 2012 . The Sleepwalkers . New York: Harper.

Collier, Paul , and Anke Hoeffler . 2004 . “ Greed and Grievance in Civil War. ” Oxford Economic Papers 56 (4): 563–595.

Corbetta, Renato . 2010 . “ Determinants of Third Parties’ Intervention and Alignment Choices in Ongoing Conflicts, 1946–2001. ” Foreign Policy Analysis 6 (1): 61–85.

Crawford, Timothy W.   2003 . Pivotal Deterrence: Third-party Statecraft and the Pursuit of Peace . Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Danilovic, Vesna . 2001 . “ Conceptual and Selection Bias Issues in Deterrence. ” Journal of Conflict Resolution 45 (1): 97–125.

Danilovic, Vesna . 2002 . When the Stakes Are High: Deterrence and Conflict among Major Powers . Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

Elman, Colin , and Michael A. Jensen , eds. 2014 . Realism Reader . New York; London: Routledge.

Fearon, James D.   1995 . “ Rationalist Explanations for War. ” International Organization 49 (3): 379–414.

Fearon, James D.   2002 . “ Selection Effects and Deterrence. ” International Interactions 28 (1): 5–30.

Fearon, James D. , and David D. Laitin . 2003 . “ Ethnicity, Insurgency, and Civil War. ” American Political Science Review 97 (1): 75–90.

Freedman, Lawrence . 2004 . Deterrence . Cambridge, MA: Polity Press.

Friedman, Thomas L.   2002 . “ Iraq Upside Down. ” New York Times , September 18, A 31.

Gaddis, John Lewis . 1986 . “ The Long Peace: Elements of Stability in the Postwar International System. ” International Security 10 (4): 99–142.

George, Alexander L.   1993 . Forceful Persuasion: Coercive Diplomacy as an Alternative to War . Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace Press.

George, Alexander L. , and Richard Smoke . 1974 . Deterrence in American Foreign Policy: Theory and Practice . New York: Columbia University Press.

George, Alexander L. , and Richard Smoke . 1989 . “ Deterrence and Foreign Policy. ” World Politics 41 (2): 170–182.

Gilpin, Robert . 1981 . War and Change in World Politics . New York: Cambridge University Press.

Gray, Colin S.   2003 . Maintaining Effective Deterrence . Carlisle, PA: Strategic Studies Institute, US Army War College.

Hamilton, Richard F. , and Holger H. Herwig , eds. 2003 . The Origins of World War I . New York: Cambridge University Press.

Harvey, Frank P.   1998 . “ Rigor Mortis or Rigor, More Tests: Necessity, Sufficiency, and Deterrence Logic. ” International Studies Quarterly 42 (4): 675–707.

Hastings, Max . 2013 . Catastrophe 1914: Europe Goes to War . New York: Vintage Books.

Huth, Paul K.   1988 . Extended Deterrence and the Prevention of War . New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Huth, Paul K.   1999 . “ Deterrence and International Conflict: Empirical Findings and Theoretical Debates. ” Annual Review of Political Science 2: 61–84.

Huth, Paul K. , and Bruce Russett . 1984 . “ What Makes Deterrence Work? Cases from 1900 to 1980. ” World Politics 36 (4): 496–526.

Huth, Paul K. , and Bruce Russett . 1988 . “ Deterrence Failure and Crisis Escalation. ” International Studies Quarterly 32 (1): 29–46.

Huth, Paul K. , and Bruce Russett . 1990 . “ Testing Deterrence Theory: Rigor Makes a Difference. ” World Politics 42 (4): 466–501.

Huth, Paul K. , and Bruce Russett . 1993 . “ General Deterrence between Enduring Rivals: Testing Three Competing Models. ” American Political Science Review 87 (1): 61–73.

Intriligator, Michael D. , and Dagobert L. Brito . 1984 . “ Can Arms Races Lead to the Outbreak of War? ” Journal of Conflict Resolution 28 (1): 63–84.

Jervis, Robert . 1979 . “ Deterrence Theory Revisited. ” World Politics 31 (2): 289–324.

Jervis, Robert . 1982/ 1983 . “ Deterrence and Perception. ” International Security 7 (3): 3–30.

Jervis, Robert . 1989 . “ Rational Deterrence: Theory and Evidence. ” World Politics 41 (2): 183–207.

Jervis, Robert , Richard Ned Lebow , and Janice Gross Stein , eds. 1985 . Psychology and Deterrence . Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.

Kang, Kyungkook , and Jacek Kugler . 2012 . “Nuclear Weapons: Stability of Terror.” In Debating a Post-American World: What Lies Ahead? , edited by Sean Clark and Sabrina Hoque , 169–175. New York: Routledge.

Kenny, Anthony . 1985 . The Logic of Deterrence . Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Keohane, Robert O.   1986 . “Theory of World Politics: Structural Realism and Beyond.” In Neorealism and Its Critics , edited by Robert O. Keohane , 1–26. New York: Columbia University Press.

Kilgour, D. Marc , and Frank C. Zagare . 1994 . “ Uncertainty and the Role of the Pawn in Extended Deterrence. ” Synthese 100 (3): 379–412.

Krauthammer, Charles . 2002 . “ The Obsolescence of Deterrence. ” Weekly Standard , December 9, 13.

Kugler, Jacek . 1984 . “ Terror without Deterrence: Reassessing the Role of Nuclear Weapons. ” Journal of Conflict Resolution 28 (3): 470–506.

Kugler, Jacek . 2012. “A World Beyond Waltz: Neither Iran nor Israel Should Have the Bomb.” http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/pages/frontline/tehranbureau/2012/09/opinion-a-world-beyond-waltz-neither-iran-nor-israel-should-have-the-bomb.html#ixzz2fwsWcK00 .

Langlois, Catherine C.   2012 . “ Power and Deterrence in Alliance Relationships: The Ally’s Decision to Renege. ” Conflict Management and Peace Science 29 (2): 148–169.

Langlois, Catherine C. , and Jean-Pierre P. Langlois . 2006 a. “ Bargaining and the Failure of Asymmetric Deterrence: Trading off the Risk of War for the Promise of a Better Deal. ” Conflict Management and Peace Science 23 (2): 159–180.

Langlois, Catherine C. , and Jean-Pierre P. Langlois . 2006 b. “ When Fully Informed States Make Good the Threat of War: Rational Escalation and the Failure of Bargaining. ” British Journal of Political Science 36 (4): 645–669.

Lebovic, James H.   2007 . Deterring International Terrorism and Rogue States: US National Security Policy after 9/11 . New York: Routledge.

Lebow, Richard Ned . 1981 . Between Peace and War: The Nature of International Crisis . Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.

Lebow, Richard Ned . 1984 . “ Windows of Opportunity: Do States Jump Through Them? ” International Security 9 (1): 147–186.

Lebow, Richard Ned , and Janice Gross Stein . 1989 . “ Rational Deterrence Theory: I Think, Therefore I Deter. ” World Politics 41 (2): 208–224.

Lebow, Richard Ned , and Janice Gross Stein . 1990 . “ Deterrence: The Elusive Dependent Variable. ” World Politics 42 (3): 336–369.

Levy, Jack . 1988 . “ When Do Deterrent Threats Work? ” British Journal of Political Science 18 (4): 485–512.

Li, Quan . 2005 . “ Does Democracy Promote or Reduce Transnational Terrorist Incidents? ” Journal of Conflict Resolution 49 (2): 278–297.

Lieber, Keir A.   2007 . “ The New History of World War I and What It Means for International Relations Theory. ” International Security 32 (2): 155–191.

Luce, R. Duncan , and Howard Raiffa . 1957 . Games and Decisions: Introduction and Critical Survey . New York: Wiley.

Machain, Carla Martinez , T. Clifton Morgan , and Patrick M. Regan . 2011 . “ Deterring Rebellion. ” Foreign Policy Analysis 7 (3): 295–316.

MacIntyre, Alasdair . 1973 . “ The Essential Contestability of Some Social Concepts. ” Ethics 84 (1): 1–9.

MacMillan, Margaret . 2013 . The War That Ended Peace: The Road to 1914 . New York: Random House.

Maurer, John H.   1995 . The Outbreak of the First World War: Strategic Planning, Crisis Decision Making, and Deterrence Failure . Westport, CT: Praeger.

Maxwell, Stephen . 1968 . Rationality in Deterrence . Adelphi Paper no. 50. London: Institute for Strategic Studies.

McMeekin, Sean . 2013 . July 1914 . New York: Basic Books.

Mearsheimer, John J.   1990 . “ Back to the Future: Instability in Europe after the Cold War. ” International Security 15 (1): 5–56.

Mearsheimer, John J.   1993 . “ The Case for a Ukrainian Nuclear Deterrent. ” Foreign Affairs 72 (3): 50–66.

Morgan, Patrick M.   2003 . Deterrence Now . Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Morgenthau, Hans J.   1948 . Politics among Nations . New York: Knopf.

Mulligan, William . 2010 . The Origins of the First World War . Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Nalebuff, Barry . 1986 . “ Brinkmanship and Nuclear Deterrence: The Neutrality of Escalation. ” Conflict Management and Peace Science 9 (2): 19–30.

New York Times . 2002 . “ In Defense of Deterrence. ” September 10, A 30.

Organski, A. F. K.   1958 . World Politics . New York: Knopf.

Organski, A. F. K. , and Jacek Kugler . 1980 . The War Ledger . Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Pape, Robert A.   2003 . “ The Strategic Logic of Suicide Terrorism. ” American Political Science Review 97 (3): 343–361.

Paul, T.V. , Patrick M. Morgan , and James J. Wirtz , eds. 2009 . Complex Deterrence: Strategy in the Global Age . Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Payne, Keith B.   2001 . The Fallacies of Cold War Deterrence and a New Direction . Lexington: University Press of Kentucky.

Pollack, Kenneth M.   2002 . “ Why Iraq Can’t Be Deterred. ” New York Times , September 26, A 31.

Posen, Barry R.   1993 . “ The Security Dilemma and Ethnic Conflict. ” Survival 35 (1): 27–47.

Powell, Robert . 1987 . “ Crisis Bargaining, Escalation, and MAD. ” American Political Science Review 81 (3): 717–735.

Press, Daryl G.   2004 . “ The Credibility of Power: Assessing Threats during the ‘Appeasement’ Crises of the 1930s. ” International Security 29 (3): 136–169.

Press, Daryl G.   2005 . Calculating Credibility: How Leaders Assess Military Threats . Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Quackenbush, Stephen L.   2004 . “ The Rationality of Rational Choice Theory. ” International Interactions 30 (2): 87–107.

Quackenbush, Stephen L.   2006 a. “ Identifying Opportunity for Conflict: Politically Active Dyads. ” Conflict Management and Peace Science 23 (1): 37–51.

Quackenbush, Stephen L.   2006 b. “ Not Only Whether but Whom: Three-party Extended Deterrence. ” Journal of Conflict Resolution 50 (4): 562–583.

Quackenbush, Stephen L.   2010 . “ General Deterrence and International Conflict: Testing Perfect Deterrence Theory. ” International Interactions 36 (1): 60–85.

Quackenbush, Stephen L.   2011 a. “ Deterrence Theory: Where Do We Stand? ” Review of International Studies 37 (2): 741–762.

Quackenbush, Stephen L.   2011 b. Understanding General Deterrence: Theory and Application . New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

Quackenbush, Stephen L. , and Frank C. Zagare . 2006 . “Game Theory: Modeling Interstate Conflict.” In Making Sense of IR Theory , edited by Jennifer Sterling-Folker , 98–114. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner.

Russett, Bruce M.   1963 . “ The Calculus of Deterrence. ” Journal of Conflict Resolution 7 (2): 97–109.

Russett, Bruce M.   1967 . “ Pearl Harbor: Deterrence Theory and Decision Theory. ” Journal of Peace Research 4 (2): 89–105.

Sartori, Anne E.   2005 . Deterrence by Diplomacy . Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Schelling, Thomas C.   1960 . The Strategy of Conflict . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Schelling, Thomas C.   1966 . Arms and Influence . New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Selten, Reinhard . 1975 . “ A Re-examination of the Perfectness Concept for Equilibrium Points in Extensive Games. ” International Journal of Game Theory 4 (1): 25–55.

Senese, Paul D. , and Stephen L. Quackenbush . 2003 . “ Sowing the Seeds of Conflict: The Effect of Dispute Settlements on Durations of Peace. ” Journal of Politics 65 (3): 696–717.

Signorino, Curt S. , and Ahmer Tarar . 2006 . “ A Unified Theory and Test of Extended Immediate Deterrence. ” American Journal of Political Science 50 (3): 586–605.

Simon, Herbert A.   1976 . “From Substantive to Procedural Rationality.” In Method and Appraisal in Economics , edited by S. J. Latsis , 129–148. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Slantchev, Branislav L.   2003 . “ The Power to Hurt: Costly Conflict with Completely Informed States. ” American Political Science Review 97 (1): 123–133.

Slantchev, Branislav L.   2011 . Military Threats: The Costs of Coercion and the Price of Peace . Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Smoke, Richard . 1987 . National Security and the Nuclear Dilemma . Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

Snyder, Glenn H.   1961 . Deterrence and Defense: Toward a Theory of National Security . Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Steinbruner, John . 1976 . “ Beyond Rational Deterrence: The Struggle for New Conceptions. ” World Politics 28 (2): 223–245.

Sudoplatov, Pavel . 1994 . Special Tasks: The Memoirs of an Unwanted Witness . Boston: Little, Brown.

Trachtenberg, Marc . 1990/ 1991 . “ The Meaning of Mobilization in 1914. ” International Security 15 (3): 120–150.

Trager, Robert F. , and Dessislava P. Zagorcheva . 2005/ 2006 . “ Deterring Terrorism: It Can Be Done. ” International Security 30 (3): 87–123.

Van Evera, Stephen . 1990/ 1991 . “ Primed for Peace: Europe After the Cold War. ” International Security 15 (3): 7–57.

Vasquez, John A.   1997 . “ The Realist Paradigm and Degenerative versus Progressive Research Programs: An Appraisal of Neotraditional Research on Waltz’s Balancing Proposition. ” American Political Science Review 91 (4): 899–912.

Verba, Sidney . 1961 . “Assumptions of Rationality and Non-rationality in Models of International Systems.” In The International System: Theoretical Essays , edited by Klaus Knorr and Sidney Verba , 93–117. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Wagner, R. Harrison . 2000 . “ Bargaining and War. ” American Journal of Political Science 44 (3): 469–484.

Walt, Stephen M.   1999 . “ Rigor or Rigor Mortis: Rational Choice and Security Studies. ” International Security 23 (4): 5–48.

Waltz, Kenneth N.   1979 . Theory of International Politics . New York: Random House.

Waltz, Kenneth N.   1981 . The Spread of Nuclear Weapons: More May Be Better . Adelphi Paper no. 171. London: Institute for Strategic Studies.

Waltz, Kenneth N.   1993 . “ The Emerging World Structure of International Politics. ” International Security 18 (2): 44–79.

Waltz, Kenneth N.   2012 . “ Why Iran Should Get the Bomb: Nuclear Balancing Would Mean Stability. ” Foreign Affairs 91 (4): 2–5.

Weede, Erich . 1983 . “ Extended Deterrence by Superpower Alliance. ” Journal of Conflict Resolution 27 (2): 231–254.

Weinberg, Gerhard L.   1995 . Germany, Hitler, and World War II . Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Werner, Suzanne . 2000 . “ Deterring Intervention: The Stakes of War and Third-Party Involvement. ” American Journal of Political Science 44 (4): 720–732.

Wu, Samuel S.G.   1990 . “ To Attack or Not to Attack: A Theory and Empirical Assessment of Extended Immediate Deterrence. ” Journal of Conflict Resolution 34 (3): 531–552.

Yuen, Amy . 2009 . “ Target Concessions in the Shadow of Intervention. ” Journal of Conflict Resolution 53 (5): 745–773.

Zagare, Frank C.   1990 . “ Rationality and Deterrence. ” World Politics 42 (2): 238–260.

Zagare, Frank C.   2004 . “ Reconciling Rationality with Deterrence: A Re-examination of the Logical Foundations of Deterrence Theory. ” Journal of Theoretical Politics 16 (2): 107–141.

Zagare, Frank C.   2011 . The Games of July: Explaining the Great War . Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

Zagare, Frank C. , and D. Marc Kilgour . 1993 . “ Modeling ‘Massive Retaliation. ’” Conflict Management and Peace Science 13 (1): 61–86.

Zagare, Frank C. , and D. Marc Kilgour . 2000 . Perfect Deterrence . Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

Zagare, Frank C. , and D. Marc Kilgour . 2003 . “ Alignment Patterns, Crisis Bargaining, and Extended Deterrence. ” International Studies Quarterly 47 (4): 587–615.

Zagare, Frank C. , and D. Marc Kilgour . 2006 . “ The Deterrence-Versus-Restraint Dilemma in Extended Deterrence: Explaining British Policy in 1914. ” International Studies Review 8 (4): 623–641.

See also Hastings (2013 , 78).

The charge was officially denied by Russian officials shortly after the publication of Sudoplatov’s book.

Classical deterrence theory is also sometimes referred to as rational deterrence theory. However, there are other theories of deterrence based on rational choice that would therefore seem to fall within the umbrella of rational deterrence theory.

For a formal model that succinctly captures the interplay between relative capability and the cost of conflict in the context of an arms race, see Intriligator and Brito (1984) . The deductions of this model are entirely consistent with the two major propositions of structural deterrence theory as well as with its policy proposals.

Not all structural deterrence theorists place a high value on logical consistency (see, e.g., Walt 1999 ), which perhaps explains why not all structural deterrence theorists endorse proliferation policies.

For a closely related theoretical construct, see Gilpin (1981) .

For example, in power transition theory, great power conflicts require both a dissatisfied challenger and a power transition. But as Zagare and Kilgour (2000 , ch. 2) show, while these two conditions may be necessary for a major power war to occur, they are not sufficient. Under complete information, wars never occur at all. And when, more likely, information is incomplete, wars occur only under certain specific conditions.

See also Hamilton and Herwig (2003) ; Mulligan (2010) ; Clark (2012) ; McMeekin (2013) ; and Hastings (2013) .

In the Rudimentary Asymmetric Deterrence Game, Defender alone has a threat that it may or may not prefer to execute. In more elaborate models, Challenger may also possess a threat to retaliate. For the details, see Zagare and Kilgour (2000) .

Most decision-theoretic deterrence theorists rely on Nash’s criterion, which is less demanding, to resolve the paradox. Powell (1987) and Nalebuff (1986) are exceptions. A Nash equilibrium, which is the standard measure of rational play in strategic-form games, is any outcome that offers no player an opportunity to induce a better outcome by unilaterally switching to another strategy. Nash equilibria, however, may be based on incredible threats (i.e., on threats of irrational choice).

Much the same can be said of power transition theory. For a trenchant counterpoint to Waltz’s (2012) argument that a nuclear armed Iran would be a stabilizing force in the Middle East, see Kugler (2012) .

See Quackenbush (2011a) for a thorough discussion of this point.

Levy (1988) and Huth (1999) provide reviews of the empirical literature on deterrence.

For example, in the Rudimentary Asymmetric Deterrence Game (figure 2 ), the only rational outcome is Status Quo if Challenger prefers Status Quo to Challenger Wins . Although Challenger’s decision to not challenge the status quo in this case is not really “successful deterrence,” it is predicted by perfect deterrence theory.

  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Institutional account management
  • Rights and permissions
  • Get help with access
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

  • Find My Rep

You are here

Research Methods in International Relations

Research Methods in International Relations

  • Christopher Lamont - Tokyo International University
  • Description

The only guide to conducting research in International Relations. Covering the full breadth of methods in IR with unrivalled clarity, this best-selling textbook takes you through the entire process of doing research, from honing your question to writing up the dissertation. The engaging and jargon-free style demystifies the process of doing research, whilst helping you develop a comprehensive understanding of the strengths and limitations of different methods and methodologies. This second edition comes with new chapters on conducting interviews and discourse analysis, as well as expanded coverage of qualitative and quantitative methods. Packed with examples, it explores the breadth of IR research today, from the long-lasting impact of colonialism to migration policy; climate change negotiations to international aid. Covering the most cutting-edge methodological developments, including critical realism, feminist, and postcolonial approaches, it helps you understand and apply research methods in world politics.

This practical introduction is essential reading for anyone setting out on their International Relations research project for the first time, at undergraduate and postgraduate levels.

Christopher Lamont is Assistant Dean of E-Track Programs and Associate Professor of International Relations at Tokyo International University, Japan .

A superb primer for those embarking on research in international relations.  The text outlines a range of approaches in a practical fashion, with references to the latest developments in theory as well as current affairs. Readers are taken through complex ideas about methods, the philosophy of knowledge and ethics with clarity, insight, and a nuanced appreciation of the value of different ways of going about inquiry in this field. Destined to become the 'go to' manual for existing IR researchers as well as the first book to recommend for those starting a PhD.

This text is an accessible introduction to International Relations research and is particularly well-suited to undergraduates embarking on their first projects. It covers the entirety of the research process, from devising questions to writing-up findings. The new chapters on interviews and discourse analysis are great additions to this second edition.

This will support learners in the research unit, there are three scopes within the research module. Learners doing a research topic will have this on their reading list for Research Skill in International Relations.

Preview this book

Sample materials & chapters, for instructors.

Please select a format:

Select a Purchasing Option

  • Electronic Order Options VitalSource Amazon Kindle Google Play eBooks.com Kobo

Help your students build critical thinking skills

Related Products

Research Methods in Politics and International Relations

  • Technical Support
  • Find My Rep

You are here

Research Methods in Politics and International Relations

Research Methods in Politics and International Relations

  • Christopher Lamont - Tokyo International University
  • Mieczyslaw P. Boduszynski - Pomona College, USA
  • Description

This is the perfect guide to conducting a research project in Politics and International Relations. From formulating a research question and conducting a literature review to writing up and disseminating your work, this book guides you through the research process from start to finish.

-        Is focused specifically on research methods in Politics and IR

-        Introduces the central methodological debates in a clear, accessible style

-        Considers the key questions of ethics and research design

-        Covers both qualitative and quantitative approaches

-        Shows you how to choose and implement the right methods in your own project

The book features two example research projects – one from Politics, one from International Relations– that appear periodically throughout the book to show you how real research looks at each stage of the process. Packed full of engaging examples, it provides you with all you need to know to coordinate your own research project in Politics and International Relations.

See what’s new to this edition by selecting the Features tab on this page. Should you need additional information or have questions regarding the HEOA information provided for this title, including what is new to this edition, please email [email protected] . Please include your name, contact information, and the name of the title for which you would like more information. For information on the HEOA, please go to http://ed.gov/policy/highered/leg/hea08/index.html .

For assistance with your order: Please email us at [email protected] or connect with your SAGE representative.

SAGE 2455 Teller Road Thousand Oaks, CA 91320 www.sagepub.com

There’s no better learning experience for political science students than carrying out an original research project. But the task can be daunting for students as well as instructors.  Research Methods in Politics and International Relations  is an excellent new resource that will be a useful companion as students set out on this endeavor.  Boduszynski and Lamont’s book is methodologically inclusive and touches on important subjects that are often overlooked, such as research ethics and publishing.

Research Methods in Politics & International Relations is a highly useful, engaging, and accessible methods textbook anchored in concise and compelling chapters and clear explanations of key dimensions of qualitative and quantitative research processes. Moreover, the book provides undergraduates with an in-depth understanding of how to design and carry out different types of research projects, ranging from research papers, capstone research projects, and senior dissertations.

Research training is more important than ever for students of Politics and International Relations at all levels. Lamont and Boduszynski provide a comprehensive, pluralist and accessible guide to the research process and the challenges and dilemmas it entails, a great resource for teachers and students alike.

Boduszynski and Lamont’s new textbook breaks new ground in promoting a comprehensive introduction to research methods in politics and international relations. I especially appreciated the unique discussion of research ethics, which provides an opportunity to reflect on the broader significance of one’s research as well as the importance of protecting human subjects. The text wholeheartedly embraces the notion of methodological pluralism, giving equal voice to a range of qualitative and quantitative methods. It does this while avoiding the divisive debates about whether some approaches are superior to others. The progression of chapters also usefully mirrors the research process, from exploring topics to writing and publishing.

“Writing Up”, Chapter 11, is an excellent resource. This is a practical chapter that presents a road map to essay writing, an outline for a thesis, and a check list for the nervous student. Beautifully, the authors remind us that "academic writing, reflecting the social phenomena that we study, is not a book reviews linear process” (p. 167), while continuing to instruct us on the contents of an introduction, the importance of the thesis or main argument, the best ways to present data and empirical analysis, and the elements all good conclusions must contain. Used in the way it was intended, as a guide to writing, a reference for further reading, and as a plan for research design, Research Methods in Politics and International Relations has the potential to improve the readability of student work and provide a template for lecturers to guide undergraduates and postgraduates alike through the minefield of research. 

Preview this book

Sample materials & chapters.

Chapter 12 - Final Hurdles and Looking Forward

For instructors

Select a purchasing option, related products.

Understanding Global Development Research

IMAGES

  1. What Is War? Defining War, Conflict and Competition

    research methods in war studies and international relations

  2. (PDF) The New History of World War I and What It Means for

    research methods in war studies and international relations

  3. Handbook of War Studies (Routledge Revivals)

    research methods in war studies and international relations

  4. War and Peace in International Relations

    research methods in war studies and international relations

  5. 15 Types of Research Methods (2023)

    research methods in war studies and international relations

  6. (PDF) The Determinants of War in International Relations

    research methods in war studies and international relations

VIDEO

  1. The US Economic War on China and BRICS

  2. War Studies Online Courses at King's College London

  3. Is Iran Ready for War? Insights on Their Involvement in the Conflict #shorts

  4. War |Strategic approaches to IR|

  5. Peace Studies vs War Studies Final Penalty + Celebrations

  6. RAND insights on the war in Ukraine, U.S. policy in the Middle East, building a more diverse teac

COMMENTS

  1. (PDF) Research Methods in International Relations

    IR itself emerged from an attempt to understand the causes of war and peace in ... science methods should be applied to study the ... Research Program in International Relations and Comparative ...

  2. The determinants of war in international relations

    Abstract. The study of warfare is one of the oldest and most important dynamics of interest for students of politics. This area of research is predominantly − but not exclusively − undertaken within the sub-field of international relations (IR). IR theorists argue that war is the contingent outcome of the interaction among variables ...

  3. Conflict, Peace and Security: An International Relations Perspective

    Conflict, peace and security are some of the enduring concerns of the Peace Research Movement of the 1950s and 1960s. They have become integrated in the dominant disciplines of international relations (IR) and political science and now are also part of most of the social science disciplines, such as economics, sociology, public policy, gender studies, international law and so on.

  4. PDF RESEARCH METHODS IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS

    Design, Methodologies in International Relations, Methodologies and Research Practice, and Research Methods for Area Studies. He holds a PhD in Politics from the University of Glasgow (2008), a MSc in International and European Politics from the University of Edinburgh (2005) and a BA in International Studies from the University of Mississippi.

  5. Case Study Methods in the International Relations Subfield

    Abstract. This article reviews the key role that case study methods have played in the study of international relations (IR) in the United States. Case studies in the IR subfield are not the unconnected, atheoretical, and idiographic studies that their critics decry. IR case studies follow an increasingly standardized and rigorous set of ...

  6. Critical methods in International Relations: The politics of techniques

    Methods have increasingly been placed at the heart of theoretical and empirical research in International Relations (IR) and social sciences more generally. This article explores the role of methods in IR and argues that methods can be part of a critical project if reconceptualized away from neutral techniques of organizing empirical material ...

  7. 20 War and History in World Politics

    War may seem a familiar category to International Relations (IR) scholars who understand their discipline to be about questions of war and peace. And historians have written many histories of wars. The aim of this essay is the uncomfortable one of making the encounter with war strange for both disciplines, in order to identify new directions ...

  8. Conflict Behavior and the Prevention of War

    DOI: 10.1177/0022343303040003006. Both historical and theoretical survey of the use of diplomacy in long-term conflict prevention. Systematizes the literature around major themes, including early warning, effective preventative strategies, and the role of international and domestic institutions in preventing conflicts.

  9. Research Methods in International Relations

    The only guide to conducting research in International Relations. Covering the full breadth of methods in IR with unrivalled clarity, this best-selling textbook takes you through the entire process of doing research, from honing your question to writing up the dissertation. The engaging and jargon-free style demystifies the process of doing ...

  10. Conflict Analysis and International Relations

    Abstract. Conflict analysis concerns the systematic study of the causes, actors, processes and resolution of conflicts around the globe. It draws upon a number of disciplines and strives to be conflict sensitive while generating relevant suggestions on how to manage and resolve conflict. The broad focus of conflict analysis is also reflected in ...

  11. Experiments in International Relations: Lab, Survey, and Field

    At conferences, at seminars, and on political science blogs, the potential utility of experimental methods for international relations (IR) research continues to be a hotly contested topic. Given the recent rise in creative applications of experimental methods, now is a useful moment to reflect more generally on the potential value of experiments to study international affairs, how these ...

  12. The debates of methodology and methods: reflections on the development

    This paper aims to explore the interplay between methods and methodologies in the field of international relations (IR) over the 100 years of its lifetime reflecting on the relationship between the rise of new research methods and the rise of new methodologies.,This paper looks in retrospect into the field's great debates using a ...

  13. Case Study Methods in International Relations

    DOI: 10.4135/9780857028051. This is a broad text on research methods in the social sciences that contains specific chapters relevant to case study research that provide a basic introduction to case study research. See in particular chapter 16, which sets out uses of case studies in social science research. George, Alexander L., and Andrew Bennett.

  14. International Relations & War

    The final application deadline is on 26 August 2024 (23:59 UK time). After the first application deadline, if the programme becomes full before the final deadlines stated above, we will close the programme to further applications. Study International Relations & War MA in the Department of War Studies at King's College London.

  15. PDF Lamont Research Methods in International Relations

    field of study in the aftermath of the First World War, when the first Chair of International Relations was established in Aberystwyth in 1919 (Burchill, 2001), and it remained a focus of inquiry throughout the Cold War as IR scholars sought to mitigate the risk of a nuclear conflict between the United States and

  16. PDF Research Methods in International Relations and Politics

    The module takes a pragmatic approach to research methods, and aims to focus on issues and advice that are relevant for most types of research in the study of international relations and politics. It does not provide training in specific methodological tools or advocate particular approaches or methods.

  17. Research Methods in International Relations

    Research methods in International Relations can be daunting to grasp, but put simply they are the tools and techniques used by students and academics to properly design research questions, and more importantly to reach persuasive and credible answers to those questions. The resources below outline the methods used in International Relations ...

  18. Process Tracing Methods

    Introduction. Process tracing is an in-depth within-case study method used in the social sciences for tracing causal mechanisms and how they play out within an actual case. Process tracing can be used to build and test theories of processes that link causes and outcomes in a bounded population of causally similar cases, in combination with ...

  19. The SAGE Handbook of Research Methods in Political Science and

    The SAGE Handbook of Research Methods in Political Science and International Relations offers a comprehensive overview of research processes in social science — from the ideation and design of research projects, through the construction of theoretical arguments, to conceptualization, measurement, & data collection, and quantitative & qualitative empirical analysis — exposited through 65 ...

  20. Modern Deterrence Theory: Research Trends, Policy Debates, and

    Although modern deterrence theories (there are more than one, and there are several variants) are generally traced back to the start of the Cold War period, they were actually conceived in the aftermath of World War I, a conflict that was brought about by the most massive failure of deterrence in the history of the international system (Maurer 1995). 1 Given the human and political carnage ...

  21. Research Methods in International Relations

    Preview. The only guide to conducting research in International Relations. Covering the full breadth of methods in IR with unrivalled clarity, this best-selling textbook takes you through the entire process of doing research, from honing your question to writing up the dissertation. The engaging and jargon-free style demystifies the process of ...

  22. Research Methods in Politics and International Relations

    Research Methods in Politics & International Relations is a highly useful, engaging, and accessible methods textbook anchored in concise and compelling chapters and clear explanations of key dimensions of qualitative and quantitative research processes. Moreover, the book provides undergraduates with an in-depth understanding of how to design and carry out different types of research projects ...

  23. Fully integrated content analysis in International Relations

    Abstract. Content analysis has once again come to the forefront of discussions regarding methods in International Relations (IR). The first wave of content analysis in IR lasted from the 1940s to the 1960s and was marked by a commitment to quantitative and manual analyses. The second wave of content analysis appeared at the start of the third ...