King's Student Law Review

Dickson poon school of law, king's college london, should britain adopt a written constitution.

(This is the second part of a three-part series on the codification of the United Kingdom)

By Isabella Reynoso

A constitution is essential for the organization of a state as it contains the fundamental principles and rules upon which a state exists (Beatson, 2010). Although the British constitution contains written sources such as statutes, it is one of few in the world that is not ‘codified into a single document, or collections of documents’ (Blick 2011: 9). As suggested by Blick (2011) this is due to the absence of a critical moment in history, such as a revolution or an independence that has made Britain reform the constitution to the extent of codifying it. Moreover, two of the most important principles of the British constitution are that it is based on parliamentary supremacy and the separation of powers. Meaning that Parliament, as opposed to a codified constitution, is the highest source of law in the UK (Dicey, 1959), and that the executive, legislative and judiciary powers shall be separate from each other. Additionally, the existence of only a few other countries in the world that do not have a codified constitution, along with recent constitutional reforms such as the Human Rights Act of 1998 and the Constitutional Reform Act of 2005, have rekindled the debate on whether or not the UK should codify its constitution (McHarg, 2008).

This essay will firstly introduce some of the proposals that have been brought forward for a written constitution. It will then argue that even though it is suggested that codifying the constitution would result in the balance of the power of the executive, further accountability, and stability, the current constitution already holds these positive factors. Additionally, Britain should not adopt a written constitution due to its history, the sources and principles of the constitution, and the practical difficulties that would result from its codification.

The debate about the codification of the British constitution has gone through a number of phases in the last thirty years (Oliver, 1992). However, most recently, suggestions for a radical reform of the constitution into a codified one have surfaced (Oliver, 1992). These have been represented by the drafting of three possible constitutions: the Macdonald Constitution, published with the Liberal Democrats federal green paper, the Tony Benn’s Constitution, ordered by the House of Commons in 1991 and the IPPR constitution. Even though these government white papers and consultation documents display different motivations for the codifications of the constitution, there are some reasons identified to be the most important, such as the balance of the power of the executive, stability, and clarity (Beatson, 2010).

Even though the British constitution is based on the separation of powers, in reality, the composition of Parliament shows that the principle is not upheld. Since the majority of ministers are members of the elected party, the executive effectively becomes part of the legislature, the highest source of law in the UK.

Therefore, it is suggested that the government can easily amend the constitution, and has too much power in its hands. Consequently, one of the suggested advantages of codifying the British constitution and abolishing Parliament as the highest source of law would be the control of the executive power by balancing it and making it accountable. (Beatson, 2010). Furthermore, it is suggested that by introducing a written constitution the control of the executive on the legislature would not effectively amount to changing the constitution. This would be further controlled by the constitutional courts.

Nevertheless, the existence of constitutional conventions, defined as habits or practices that regulate constitutional behaviour and the conduct of public office holders (Bradley and Ewing, 2011), already balance the power of the executive and hold it accountable in a more efficient way than the courts would (Blick, 2011). For example, if the voting population were to refuse to tolerate the breach of a constitutional convention, the executive would probably find itself accused of being illegitimate. As rightly argued by Jennings, if conventions are ignored, it results in severe political repercussions (Chand, 1938). An example of this would be the rejection of the House of Lords to pass the budget in 1909. The Lords’ actions undoubtedly breached a convention, and by refusing to pass a Finance Bill there were political repercussions. After a prolonged crisis, the Parliament Act of 1911 incorporated the convention into primary legislation (Leyland, 2012). Additionally, the statement that “Parliament may pass many laws, which many people do not want, but it never passes any laws, which any substantial section of the population violently dislikes” (Ewing 2004: 741), supports this. It is subsequently argued that constitutional conventions are not legally binding, unclear and therefore the supposed ‘check’ that the current constitution exerts on the executive is not demanding and solid enough (Beatson, 2010). However, the fact that the executive would probably face political difficulties and that it is likely to find itself accused as illegitimate if it breaches an important convention, unquestionably constitutes a valid argument against the allegation that the current constitution neither balances the power of the executive, nor does it hold the executive to account.

Additionally, it is suggested that by codifying the constitution and having an entrenched document as the highest source of law instead of Parliament, the constitution would be more stable as it will be more difficult to amend (Beatson, 2010). Nonetheless, if it were to be codified, it would be a definite step towards depriving the constitution of one of its most important characteristics:its flexibility. The flexibility, which the British constitution is recognized for, is essential “to ensure that the legal framework of the constitution is operated in accordance with the prevailing constitutional values of the period” (Bradley and Ewing 2011: 25). This allows changes to be made to the constitution according to the current political and social circumstances. As supported by Bogdanor, Khaitan and Vogenauer (2007) the lack of a codified constitution means that Britain did not need to formulate a statements or laws Doing so  would quickly render it redundant as a result of political change. For example, a constitution, which was drafted in 1830, would have included declarations about voting rights and the powers of the House of Lords, which would have become redundant after the Great Reform Act of 1832, Parliament(Bogdanor, Khaitan and Vogenauer, 2007). Additionally, the constitution’s flexibility allows the uncomplicated development and change within the constitution, while its legal aspect remains unaffected (Allen and Thompson, 2011). An example of this would be the creation of the ‘Sewel Convention’ in 1999, which prohibited Parliament from legislating on matters that had been devolved to the Scottish Parliament without obtaining its consent beforehand. Therefore, as stated by Professor Ringen in Blick (2011: 9), “The British constitution is a complex and evolving living organism” characterized by its flexibility which proves as an evident advantage for society due to the possibility of the constitution to evolve with society and current political values.

Moreover, one of the most important reasons put forward for the codification of the constitution is the fact that it would provide a clearer and more accessible account of the fundamental rules and principles according to which the state is established and governed (Bogdanor, Khaitan and Vogenauer, 2007). Nevertheless, the practical difficulties that would result from codifying the constitution far outweigh the advantage of making the constitution easier to access for the public. First of all, as stated by Blick (2011), the precise content of the constitution would be difficult to determine. This is due to the unwritten sources of the constitution such as conventions, that while constituting an extremely important source, are mostly undefined and not legally binding. It is suggested that it would be advantageous to gather the conventions on a specific subject together, preventing them from losing their flexibility while accommodating some of the advantages of codification such as clarity and organization (Ewing, 2004). However, it would be an obvious disadvantage to include them in the constitution as legally binding obligations, as they are not only difficult to define but they would also would loose their essence of binding purely on a non-legal basis. Furthermore, the fact that the British constitution is based on parliamentary sovereignty presents another difficulty if it were to be codified. This is supported by Blick (2011) who states that “There is either a direct choice between the retention of parliamentary supremacy or a written constitution”, implying that there would be an obvious clash against Britain’s most important constitutional principle.

Therefore, even though it is suggested that codifying the constitution would lead to further accountability, balance, stability and clarity, the current constitution already holds these positive aspects. Additionally, as stated by Barber in Parpworth (2012) Britain’s constitution has been a success for years and has produced a stable government in terms of democracy, transparency, and human rights. Therefore, the British constitution should not be codified because this would only bring practical difficulties, constituting a substantial step towards depriving the British constitution of its flexibility

  • Allen, M. and Thompson, B. (ed.) (2011) Cases and Materials on Constitutional and Administrative Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Beatson, J. (2010) Reforming an unwritten constitution. Law Quarterly Review 48: 1-17.
  • Blick, A. (2011) Codifying-or not codifying- the UK constitution: A literal Review. Centre for Political and Constitutional Studies, Kings College London. 4-32.
  • Bogdanor, V, Khaitan, T, and Vogenauer, S. (2007) Should Britain Have a Written Constitution? The Political Quarterly 78/4: 499-517.
  • Bradley, A. W. and Ewing, K. D. (ed.) (2011) Constitutional and Administrative Law . Essex: Pearson.
  • Chand, B. (1938) Conventions of the Constitution. Journal of Comparative Legislation and International Law 20/4: 222-229.                     Retrieved 29 th January 2013 from: http://www.jstor.org/stable/755034.
  • Dicey, A. V.  (1959) The Law of The Constitution . London: Macmillan and Co Ltd.
  • Ewing, K.D. (2004) The Law and the Constitution: Manifesto of the Progressive Party. The Modern Law Review 67/5: 734-752.
  • Leyland, P. (ed.) (2012) The Constitution of the United Kingdom. Portland: Hart Publishing.
  • McHarg, A. (2008) Reforming the United Kingdom Constitution: Law, Convention, Soft Law. The Modern Law Review 71/6: 853-877.
  • Oliver, D. (1992) Written Constitutions: Principles and Problems. Parliamentary Affairs 42/2: 135-152.
  • Parpworth, N . (ed.) (2012) Constitutional and Administrative Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Leave a Reply Cancel reply

You must be logged in to post a comment.

  • Work & Careers
  • Life & Arts

Become an FT subscriber

Try unlimited access Only $1 for 4 weeks

Then $75 per month. Complete digital access to quality FT journalism on any device. Cancel anytime during your trial.

  • Global news & analysis
  • Expert opinion
  • Special features
  • FirstFT newsletter
  • Videos & Podcasts
  • Android & iOS app
  • FT Edit app
  • 10 gift articles per month

Explore more offers.

Standard digital.

  • FT Digital Edition

Premium Digital

Print + premium digital, weekend print + standard digital, weekend print + premium digital.

Today's FT newspaper for easy reading on any device. This does not include ft.com or FT App access.

  • 10 additional gift articles per month
  • Global news & analysis
  • Exclusive FT analysis
  • Videos & Podcasts
  • FT App on Android & iOS
  • Everything in Standard Digital
  • Premium newsletters
  • Weekday Print Edition
  • FT Weekend Print delivery
  • Everything in Premium Digital

Essential digital access to quality FT journalism on any device. Pay a year upfront and save 20%.

  • Everything in Print

Complete digital access to quality FT journalism with expert analysis from industry leaders. Pay a year upfront and save 20%.

Terms & Conditions apply

Explore our full range of subscriptions.

Why the ft.

See why over a million readers pay to read the Financial Times.

International Edition

LSE - Small Logo

  • Write for us
  • LSE Comment
  • Economy and Society
  • Post-Brexit Policy
  • Artificial Intelligence

December 23rd, 2011

The challenge for those who wish to codify the uk’s constitution is to make it relevant to voters who may have more pressing concerns..

1 comment | 1 shares

Estimated reading time: 5 minutes

should the uk codify its constitution essay

On December 8 th the House of Commons Committee on Political and Constitutional Reform held a hearing on whether or not the UK should consider codifying its political arrangements thus moving towards a written constitution. I was asked to give evidence along with former Labour MP and Cabinet Minister Tony Benn and Richard Gordon QC. Each of us is on the record as favouring a written constitution – Tony Benn having actually submitted a bill to Parliament and Richard having also drafted a proposal.

The Committee has been set up to monitor the terms of reference of the office of the Deputy Prime Minister (held by Nick Clegg) whose responsibilities include constitutional reform. The hearings on codification are not prompted by any specific item on the political agenda. They are a ‘mapping’ exercise designed to look into the advantages and disadvantages of any such move; they will be held on an occasional basis with the aim of producing a report by the end of this parliament. If the parliament runs for its full term, the report of the Committee could provide a contemporary backdrop to the celebration of the 800 th anniversary of the Magna Carta in 2015.

Among the huge list of difficulties that would have to be overcome in any move towards a written constitution there are two very practical considerations. The first is that constitutional reform is not a ‘hot button’ issue for public opinion. On the contrary I indicated in my remarks to the Committee that trying to demonstrate salience to voters would be an enormous challenge. I suggested that the target citizen is not a civil rights activist but a working mother who is multi-tasking. The case for codification has to seem relevant to her. Ratification in my view would have to pass a double test – a minimum proportion of eligible voters would need to give their assent and there should be a majority in favour in each part of the UK. This double hurdle would provide an incentive for anyone drawing up a constitution to ensure that it is really relevant to voters and that most people will be comfortable with it.

The second practical challenge revolves around the question of the constitutional ‘moment’ – the question of what events in the real world would make codification a priority concern. Historically it is easy to identify external shocks as a trigger for a written constitution (for example Soviet withdrawal from Central Europe) or an internal crisis (such as the Arab Spring). I suggested that a different type of trigger is identified in the constitutional economics tradition of Nobel Prize winner James Buchanan, which looks at the event of major changes to the assignment of powers in a multi level system of government. Such changes require powers to be clearly defined, the conditions for their exercise to be clear and for safeguards to be put in place for how they are to be interpreted and exercised. In theory all of these changes are likely to prompt a move towards written arrangements. The current situation in the UK can be characterised by movements of power, not only between the UK and the EU but also between Westminster and the devolved parts of the UK.  However there is still a step between theory and practice.

A very traditional British objection to a written constitution is that such a document introduces an unhelpful rigidity into arrangements and overlooks the importance of unwritten conventions. I suggested in my remarks that any written arrangements had to provide for both soft rules (where there is flexibility) and hard rules that are prescriptive.  As an example of the importance of the issue I cited the example of the current debate about fiscal rules in the form of balanced budget stipulations.  The US seems to have gone cool on the idea of hard rules – perhaps because of the difficulty of formulating the rule over an economic cycle, and perhaps because of the incentives created for escape mechanisms through the use of off-balance sheet devices such as guarantees and insurance schemes. The Eurozone, on the other hand, is moving towards hard rules.

Tony Benn reminded the Committee that in a democracy the people are the sovereign and not Parliament. Parliament acts on their behalf. This led to a discussion of the role of referendums. In Germany there is a deep aversion to referendums because the historical record showed that they could be used by governments to manipulate public opinion. I also pointed to other – less disastrous – cautionary tales such as the California example of popular initiatives that go in contradictory directions, the Swiss example of voting ‘every Sunday’ with populists getting their moment in the sun, and the Irish tale of people voting on a question different from that on the ballot. The conditions surrounding the use of referendums therefore had to be carefully framed and their use placed outside the hands of governments.

The hearings of the Committee are not technical; they are not about drafting actual provisions nor do they in any way prejudge whether or not the UK should move towards codification. Nevertheless, it is very useful to have an exercise that clears some of the ground, identifies some of the elephant traps and addresses some of the more basic concerns and possible misunderstandings so that any future changes can be based on sound judgments.

Please read our  comments policy  before posting.

Frank Vibert gave evidence to the House of Commons’ Political and Constitutional Reform Committee on 8 December. View the session on Parliament TV .

____________________________________

About the author

Print Friendly, PDF & Email

An important question today is whether a constitution _can_ be codified. The conditions under which the Americans codified their constitutional framework in 1787 were radically different from what obtains anywhere in the world today. Among other things, the US Constitution was drafted and ratified in express violation of the procedures set forward in the Articles of Confederation. And for better or worse, that model arguably remains _the_ model. Japan adopted the Meiji Constitution in 1890; it was drastically modified under the Potsdam Declaration at the end of World War II. . . . Another example of very undemocratic adoption of democratic procedural frameworks.

Can a well-formed constitution be codified in a robustly democratic way?

Leave a Comment Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Notify me of follow-up comments by email.

Notify me of new posts by email.

Related Posts

should the uk codify its constitution essay

If we wish to hold MPs to account through some form of recall, then we should at least identify what we think they should be doing

June 11th, 2014.

should the uk codify its constitution essay

Scottish local elections in 2012 show that voters have understood the STV system and are not put-off by it

October 4th, 2012, cameron’s approach to a british bill of rights lacks solutions and is essentially unconservative in nature, august 2nd, 2012, whatever the result, thursday’s referendum will not mean the end of the road for electoral reform in the uk, may 4th, 2011.

X

The Constitution Unit

What is the UK Constitution?

Menu

The UK is often said to have an ‘unwritten’ constitution.  This is not strictly correct.  It is largely written, but in different documents.  But it has never been codified, brought together in a single document. In this respect, the UK is different from most other countries, which have codified constitutions. But not all: New Zealand and Israel also lack a codified constitution. 

Codified constitutions are typically produced following a major historic turning point, such as the grant of independence, revolution, defeat in war, or complete collapse of the previous system of government.  None of these things have happened to the UK, which is why it has never had cause to codify its constitution. (Our one revolution, in the 17 th  century, did briefly produce a written constitution: Cromwell’s Instrument of Government).

This is the reason why the UK has not felt the need to codify its constitution.  But the UK does have a constitution, to be found in leading statutes, conventions, judicial decisions, and treaties.  Examples of constitutional statutes include the Bill of Rights 1689, Acts of Union 1707 and 1800, Act of Settlement 1701, Parliament Acts 1911 and 1949, Human Rights Act 1998, Scotland Act, Northern Ireland Act and Government of Wales Act 1998.  Examples of conventions include that the monarch acts on ministerial advice; that the Prime Minister sits in the House of Commons; that the Queen appoints as Prime Minister the person most likely to command the confidence of the House of Commons.  These and other conventions have themselves been codified in documents such as the Cabinet Manual.   

Parliamentary sovereignty is commonly regarded as the defining principle of the British Constitution. This is the ultimate law-making power vested in the UK parliament to create or abolish any law. But parliament can limit its law making power, as in the Human Rights Act; or devolve legislative power, as in the Scotland Act. Other core principles of the British Constitution include the rule of law, the separation of government into executive, legislative, and judicial branches, the accountability of ministers to parliament, and the independence of the judiciary.  

The main disadvantage of an uncodified constitution is that it is harder to understand. Another is that it is easier to amend than in countries with written constitutions with elaborate amendment procedures.  But this flexibility can also be seen as an advantage: it has enabled the removal of hereditary peers from the House of Lords, introduction of the Human Rights Act, devolution to Scotland, Wales, and Northern Ireland, and creation of the Supreme Court.  

The UK constitution has multiple guardians. These include  the Supreme Court , in its constitutional judgements (such as  Miller/Cherry in 2019 ); the House of Lords Constitution Committee, and the Commons Public Administration and Constitutional Affairs Committee; the Lord Chancellor; and specific constitutional watchdogs, such as the Judicial Appointments Commission, or the Electoral Commission.  

Since the vote to leave the EU,  some have suggested  that the UK faces a ‘constitutional moment’ which might lead to a codified constitution. But the difficulties of agreeing a written constitution should not be underestimated, and the democratic benefits of a written constitution should not be exaggerated.

Related explainers: 

  • What is a constitution? 
  • What are constitutional conventions? 

Related research: 

  • Designing a constitutional convention  
  • Democracy in the UK After Brexit  
  • Rebuilding constitutional standards: five questions for the next Conservative leader

Read our briefings

Sign up to our mailing list

Read our explainers

Read our publications

culogo

Read our blog

Tel: +44 (0)20 7679 4977 Email:  [email protected]

Find us >

  • Search Menu
  • Advance articles
  • Author Guidelines
  • Submission Site
  • Open Access
  • Why Submit?
  • About Oxford Journal of Legal Studies
  • About University of Oxford Faculty of Law
  • Editorial Board
  • Advertising and Corporate Services
  • Journals Career Network
  • Self-Archiving Policy
  • Dispatch Dates
  • Journals on Oxford Academic
  • Books on Oxford Academic

Issue Cover

Article Contents

1. introduction, 2. constitution and codification, 3. constitution and the people, 4. constitution and pouvoir constituant mixte, 5. conclusion.

  • < Previous

A Written Constitution: A Case Not Made

ORCID logo

London School of Economics and Political Science, Department of Law. Email: [email protected] . I would like to thank Conor Gearty, Eric Heinze, David Kershaw, Nicola Lacey, Martin Loughlin, Emmanuel Melissaris and Neil Walker for their comments and suggestions.

  • Article contents
  • Figures & tables
  • Supplementary Data

Jo Eric Khushal Murkens, A Written Constitution: A Case Not Made, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies , Volume 41, Issue 4, Winter 2021, Pages 965–986, https://doi.org/10.1093/ojls/gqab016

  • Permissions Icon Permissions

Whether the UK needs a written constitution is a staple of British constitutional debates. Over the years, the fault lines have shifted from whether to incorporate a Bill of Rights to much deeper disagreement with respect to the people and the central power of the state. In this article I neither endorse the conservative case against a written constitution nor argue for the existing constitution to be codified. Instead, I first assess the content of various proposals for a written constitution. I then problematise the process of constitution making by asking not whether the UK constitution should be codified, but by relating the constitution to the people as the authors and to the state as its object.

Should the UK adopt a codified constitution? The question is one that is energetically debated. The argument for a codified constitution seems obvious. It is commonly assumed that written constitutions would tidy-up the existing arrangements. Internal housekeeping would not only bring the UK into line with almost all other states that have codified constitutions (the exceptions are Israel, New Zealand, Sweden and Saudi Arabia), but would also improve the quality of public discussions through better knowledge about governmental processes and institutional arrangements. The central benefit of codification would, therefore, be ‘clarity and definiteness’. 1

The symbolic 800th anniversary of Magna Carta in 2015 and the ongoing implications of the EU referendum in 2016 have added to the chorus of commentators spelling out the virtues of written constitutions. EU withdrawal had an immediate impact on every aspect of government, from the status of referendums, the relationship between popular and parliamentary sovereignty, the politicisation of the civil service, the contemporary use of prerogative powers, relations between the executive, the legislature and the judiciary, and, finally, to the Union itself. The process of withdrawal has left the unwritten constitution in ‘crisis’, 2 in a ‘molten’ condition, 3 and has highlighted the need for a written constitution.

In this article I will assess the arguments that have been advanced in favour of codification, as well as the content of the draft constitutional proposals that have been published over the last 30 years. Most of the proposals satisfy the formal qualities of clarity, concision and coherence. They do so primarily by preserving the existing structures of government in a singular and hierarchical constitutional document for a unitary state. The constitutional proposals are drafted in the language of the rational constitution that articulates the monolithic idioms of sovereignty, ultimate authority, entrenchment, enforceability, uniformity, unity and finality. So far, so modern. But the territorial politics of the UK suggests that codification will not succeed as a ‘completely theorised agreement’ 4 that conveys the clarity of constitutional law, the unity of constituent power and the common identity of a national people. Instead of providing the solution to the crisis, codification begs the constitutional question: it assumes the structures of government, the existence of a people and the integrity of the state when all these issues need to be problematised, interrogated and reconstructed before they can be written down and applied across the UK.

Apart from being an essential piece of good housekeeping, written constitutions are also viewed as a civic covenant to enhance the rationality, humanity and inclusivity of a representative democracy based on popular sovereignty. 5 In the second section of the article I relate the idea of a written constitution to the people who are meant to authorise it, and to the state which it is supposed to serve. The connections between constitution, people and state are, of course, axiomatic. However, the act of writing a constitution oscillates between contradictory but mutually dependent processes that locate the authority of the people not simply in popular consent, but also in a system of human rights. And whereas constitution making necessarily reinforces the centralised governance structures, in a union state it must also accommodate the decentralised structures with respect to territory, population and government. A civic covenant is an ongoing conversation that strikes a balance between advancing clarity and openness and finding closure. It initiates a never-ending dialectic of mutual construction and ambivalent relations: the constitution constructs the government, the people and the state, which in turn explain the constitution. Those making the case for a written constitution need to provide more information about which aspects are fixed, flexible and foreclosed.

Codification will only succeed as an ‘incompletely theorised agreement’ that recognises ambiguity and lack of clarity, reconciles formally contradictory principles, harnesses opposing dynamics and acknowledges difference. A written constitution should not be a ‘freeze frame’, generated by a still image of the constitution taken at a particular moment. It should instead result from a long exposure to transitional processes of redefinition and renewal. The question should not ask whether it is desirable for the UK to adopt a written constitution, but how the UK should be reconstituted.

Constitution making is a political act. Choosing the basic principles of constitutional design, endowing the document with legitimacy and ensuring its utility as a political artefact combines ‘science, art and craft’. 6 But constitution making, especially in a country like the UK, would necessitate deep changes for the legal and political culture, 7 especially if the constitution replaced Acts of Parliament as the highest source of law. The doctrine of parliamentary supremacy, together with the rule of law and conventions, forms the backbone of the UK’s unwritten constitution. It has always been and remains a totemic issue in constitutional debates. As the highest source of law, Acts of Parliament may violate international law and fundamental rights and repeal constitutional statutes at will. The UK Supreme Court may have attempted to disaggregate parliamentary supremacy by intimating that, in the context of rights, the doctrine is ‘no longer … absolute’, 8 but in the context of the devolved governance structures, the same court has deemed Westminster’s power to legislate for Scotland and Wales to be ‘undiminished’. 9 Martin Loughlin and Stephen Tierney argue that this dominant institutional conception of absolute legislative authority is a ‘primitive view’ that ‘rests on an inchoate appeal to the need for Westminster to hold on to untrammelled power [which] is inadequate and must be jettisoned’. 10 This primitive view is most incompatible with, and therefore most threatened by, the adoption of a written constitution. If it is retained, the UK will remain ‘incapable of being constitutionalised’. 11 If it is repudiated, the culture of the matchless, flexible, political constitution will have been corrupted. Rooted in conservatism 12 and anti-rationalism, 13 and sceptical of the constitutional responsibilities of courts, 14 opponents view the idea of a written constitution as ‘unnecessary, undesirable and un-British’. 15 As Roger Scruton has observed:

Conservatives in the British tradition are heirs to an island culture, in which custom prevails over reason as the final court of appeal … When interrogated as to the justice or reasonableness of any particular part of their inheritance—be it the common law, the monarchy, the nature and workings of parliament, the Anglican Church and its nonconformist offshoots—they tend either to shrug their shoulders, asserting that this is how things are because that is how they were, or else they take refuge in irony and self-mockery, confessing to the absurdity of a system whose principal merit is that nobody knows why it exists, and hence nobody quite knows why it shouldn’t. 16

The ‘era of constitutional reform’ since 1997 has been formed by landmark legislation and institutional changes. 17 Although these changes indicate a lack of faith in the traditional constitution, they also demonstrate an absence of political will for a new constitution. The process was not guided by clear mechanisms or overarching principles. Some decisions, eg on continued membership of, and withdrawal from, the European Union (1975; 2016) and on devolution and mayoral referendums (since 1998), involved plebiscites. Some legislation, like the Human Rights Act 1998, was preceded by a government White Paper explaining the policy. 18 Others changes, such as the reform of the office of the Lord Chancellor (2003) and the inauguration of the UK Supreme Court (2009), took place even without public consultation. Arguably, the domestic reforms are linked by the gradual embracing of the doctrine of separation of powers. 19 However, separation of powers is ‘a newfound religion, not much revealed in Government scripture before 2003’. 20

Over the past 50 years, 21 a number of judges, scholars, politicians and think tanks have put forward their arguments for codification and, in a handful of cases, have taken the time and effort to produce a draft constitution. On the conservative side, Lord Hailsham called for a new constitution and Bill of Rights in the 1970s. 22 On the liberal side, Lord Scarman gave lectures over three decades in support of a written constitution. 23 Charter 88, a pressure group, backed constitutional and electoral reform with the support of Gordon Brown, 24 who supported a written constitution also as Prime Minister. 25 In 1991, the Institute for Public Policy Research (IPPR) produced a 136-page long ‘constitution’, which consisted of 129 articles and six schedules. 26 In 1993, Tony Benn wrote a radical proposal for a reconstitution of the UK as a Federal Commonwealth with an elected Head of State. 27 Oxford students drafted a constitution, under supervision, in 2006, 28 and Richard Gordon published a draft constitution with 248 clauses in 2010. 29 In the same year, Vernon Bogdanor and Stephen Hockman led a ‘constitution working group’ that identified problems, questions, and options with respect to codification. 30 The debate intensified in the run-up to the 800th anniversary of Magna Carta in 2015. 31 The House of Commons Political and Constitutional Reform Committee (HCPCRC) set out three models of a codified constitution (a declaratory Code, a Consolidation Act and a Written Constitution) and, following a nationwide consultation, found broad popular support for codification. 32 From 2013 to 2015, the LSE’s Institute of Public Affairs crowd-sourced a 30-page long ‘People’s Constitution’. 33 Since the referendum on EU withdrawal in 2016, a steadfast number of lectures, 34 debates, 35 broadcasts, 36 newspaper articles, 37 reports 38 and publications 39 have corroborated the growing concerns with codification. In the December 2019 General Election, parties as diverse as the Liberal Democrats, the Brexit Party, the Green Party and the Alliance Party of Northern Ireland advocated a written constitution for the UK. 40

The constitutional proposals give rise to two sets of questions. First, what is the purpose of codification? Is it to clarify the rules of government? Or is it to regulate the more intricate relationship between the people and the state? Secondly, how ‘un-British’ are the draft constitutional proposals? Would a written constitution reflect ‘the soul of a nation’ by faithfully translating the UK’s cultural, political and legal tradition into written form? Or would codification fire up the ‘engine of social transformation’ and reconstitute the nation by creating a framework for a different political order and an aspirational future? 41

The primary function of a constitution is to serve as an instrument of government. Enabling rules set out a formal framework for the basic rules that regulate the activity of governing within a state and authorise decision making. Nominal or organisational constitutions 42 are limited to

the set of laws, rules and practices that create the basic institutions of the state, and its component and related parts, and stipulate the powers of those institutions and the relationship between the different institutions and between those institutions and the individual. 43

The primary concern of all the draft proposals lies with clarifying the structures of government and fundamental rights. Most of them would preserve the hereditary monarchy, the Church of England, the adversarial political system and, worryingly, the doctrine of parliamentary supremacy. 44 Most of them display no enthusiasm for higher-law constitutional limits on Parliament’s law-making ability. Although the most recent Written Constitution by the HCPCRC confers a power on the UK Supreme Court to review the compliance of Acts of Parliament with the Constitution, it only empowers the Court in cases of non-compliance to ‘make a declaration of unconstitutionality that does not invalidate the statutory provision in question’. 45

The conservative nature of the codification debate in the UK is intensified by the conservative nature of the codification process itself. Comparative experience suggests that creating a constitution is constrained by collective choices (the goals, the mechanisms), 46 but also by the imagination of the drafters, which ‘is framed by what already exists’. 47 The modesty of the British debate creates a tension between constitutional replacement and constitutional conservation. The authors of the constitutional proposals typically set out to ‘change the basis of the Constitution’, 48 ‘to chart a new course’ 49 and to replace the ‘out-dated dogma’. 50 But most of the constitutional prototypes end up displaying a cognitive preference for the central features of the unwritten constitution, albeit in codified form. The comparatively progressive proposal by the IPPR in 1991 has to concede that ‘much of the content is in the best (or worst) tradition of gradualism. The main features of the present Constitution are left more or less intact.’ 51 Although Richard Gordon’s draft breaks ground by empowering the people and subjecting Parliament to the constitution, in all other respects he aims ‘to collate in written form much of our existing informal constitution’. 52 If the purpose of codification is to conserve constitutional choices that already exist, would the adoption of a written constitution still be ‘a pre-eminently political act’? 53 Would it even be a meaningful one? In the following paragraphs I will assess the reasons given in support of codification.

If one were to believe the literature, the main benefit of having a written constitution would lie in improving the quality of the debate by generating knowledge and clarifying the laws of the constitution. Education, according to Robert Blackburn, ‘is one of the strongest arguments for having one’. 54 A constitution that sets out the basic rules, procedures and institutions of government would act as a guide for all public office holders, as well as ‘a reference point in everyone’s upbringing and education’. 55 Opinion polls support the need for political education and legal clarity. Ipsos Mori found in 2008 that only 20% of the respondents believed they knew the UK’s governing arrangements ‘very well or fairly well’. 56 In 2018, almost two-thirds (65%) of respondents in a YouGov poll wanted ‘a written constitution providing clear legal rules within which government ministers and civil servants are forced to operate’. 57 In 2019, that percentage jumped up to 72% on a very similar question in a ComRes/Daily Express poll. 58 In 2015, the HCPCRC acknowledged the clear popular support for a written constitution in opinion polls as well as its ‘beneficial educative effect in society, for young persons at school and the country in general’. 59

However, public edification is not the purpose of constitutions. 60 A constitution may have an educational effect , but that is very different from it being an objective. In addition, it is far from clear that a comprehensive constitutional code would result in a ‘pocket constitution’ (a printed copy that fits in a pocket or purse)—a metonym for ease of reference and accessibility. In 2013, the Comparative Constitutions Project pulled together the UK’s extant constitutional statutes from Magna Carta 1297 to the Fixed-term Parliaments Act 2011. 61 Without including judicial decisions, prerogative powers, conventions or parliamentary custom and governmental practices, the final document exceeded 700 pages and consisted of 225,000 words—almost the length of James Joyce’s Ulysses . India usually tops the league table for the longest codified constitution in the world, at 146,000 words spread over 444 articles in 22 parts with 118 schedules. But, as James Melton and his colleagues, who oversaw the Project, note, the UK has the ‘longest and, arguably, the most complex constitution in the world’. 62

The HCPCRC’s proposals fare better in that respect. Their Constitutional Consolidation Act consists of 231 articles over 239 pages, whilst their Written Constitution contains 53 articles over 74 pages. In terms of length and style, especially the Written Constitution purports to be more of a ‘layman’s’ (as opposed to a lawyer’s) document, as Franklin Delano Roosevelt called it in dated terms, in that it strives to ‘enable everyone to know what the rules and institutions were that governed and directed ministers, civil servants and parliamentarians in performing their public duties’. 63 It does so by clarifying the powers of the Crown, the government’s prerogative powers, the legal status of referendums and human rights, the role of the devolved administrations and the competences of the devolved parliaments. But mainly it succeeds in doing so by maintaining the status quo: ‘we deliberately did not set out to propose constitutional codification with radical constitutional reform’. 64

The written form and the organisational substance do not complete the concept of constitution. According to Giovanni Sartori, the form is only a means, when ‘what really matters is the end, the telos ’, 65 namely the purpose of the framework, which is the prevention of over-concentration and arbitrary power. For the past 250 years, this telos has placed limitations on government: ‘it is undeniable that the whole of the American tradition has understood “constitution” as a means for “limited government”’. 66 In the standard account, governmental decision making is ‘disabled’ by subjecting the political decision-making process to substantive requirements (Bill of Rights) and by the existence of procedural obstacles to constitutional amendment (higher voting thresholds, referendum requirements). However, it is important to note that enabling rules and disabling rules are complementary, not contradictory. Drawing on John Searle, Stephen Holmes argues that a modern constitution does not limit government, but it does enhance democracy. Searle and Holmes distinguish between regulative rules which control a pre-existing activity (eg ‘no smoking’) and constitutive rules which initiate and enable an activity (eg ‘bishops move diagonally’). 67 The political and legal systems consist of both enabling and disabling rules. The linchpin is the constitution, which legitimates the exercise of state power by providing ‘political solutions for the problem of the self-reference of the legal system and legal solutions for the problem of the self-reference of the political system’. 68

Advocates for a written constitution and a Bill of Rights do not view enabling and disabling rules as complementary. But nor do they fully embrace the telos of limited government. The debate about a Bill of Rights has in the past acted as a proxy for a written constitution, and it sheds more light on the projected relationship between the people and the state. The government’s Green Paper in July 2007 envisaged a ‘British Bill of Rights and Duties’. 69 A government commission referred to the existing framework of ‘rights and responsibilities’. 70 As is clear from the qualifying concepts of duties and responsibilities, from the government’s perspective rights ‘must be exercised in a way that respects the human rights of others’. 71 In 2008, the Joint Committee on Human Rights unequivocally recommended the adoption of a ‘Bill of Rights and Freedoms’ without, however, recommending entrenchment against future amendment or repeal by requiring a special parliamentary majority or referendum requirement. ‘In our view such forms of entrenchment are not compatible with our tradition of parliamentary democracy which has carefully preserved the freedom of each Parliament to legislate according to its view of the public interest.’ 72 Once more, parliamentary sovereignty is viewed as a value greater than rights protection, stifling the significance of codification from the outset. The Joint Committee also formed the view that, although economic and social rights, such as health, education and housing, should be included in a Bill of Rights, individual litigants would not be able to enforce those rights against the government or any public authority. 73 Whereas in other contexts human rights assert inspirational values and aspirational principles as universal, inalienable, indivisible and refer to all persons as human beings, not as citizens, 74 ‘British’ human rights would be qualified by duties, responsibilities and the enhancement of ‘our liberties’ for ‘our citizens’ in ‘our country’. 75

Human rights are supposed to be justifiable uniquely and ‘exclusively from a moral point of view’, 76 as opposed to ethical or pragmatic considerations. By way of contrast, the British proposals justify human rights on grounds of their instrumental value ‘to ensure that the system works better to protect the individual against the powerful’. 77 It is true that human rights offer functional protections from arbitrary government on an individual basis through disabling rules. But that tells only one half of the story, making it still a ‘very British’ story. Rights are also enabling rules that facilitate the communicative conditions for ‘democratic opinion- and will-formation that justify the presumption that outcomes are rationally acceptable’. 78 This is the point about their objective moral justification. The concept of human rights is oriented towards the common good, which is constructed through the discursive articulation of individual rights into a comprehensive system of public rights. The legally guaranteed protection of the private autonomy of the individual may be the focal point of lawyers, politicians and society in general. But conceptually, it is a condition for the political autonomy of citizens which is realised using reason. In the same way that enabling and disabling rules are complementary, the two sides of human rights are also interdependent. 79

Almost without exception, current proposals for codification would not remodel the structures of government but affirm them. Codification would not involve a caesura with the existing order, but produce ‘greater clarity, wider and deeper dispersal of power, and a firmer more enforceable set of principles and rules’. 80 Codification would protect rights, but not alter the current scope of rights protection. A written constitution would systematise historical social practices, not equate to an act of rational design. In short, as things stand, constitution making would be neither a political nor a cultural act. The British debate has successfully depoliticised the arguments for codification and neutralised the possibility of cultural reform. The options for the drafters are bounded by a status quo bias and by constitutional imaginations that are steeped in British political culture.

Men make their own history, but not of their own free will; not under circumstances they themselves have chosen but under the given and inherited circumstances with which they are directly confronted. The tradition of the dead generations weighs like a nightmare on the minds of the living. 81

The draft proposals purport to clarify the rules of government to bring about a new constitutional paradigm. The proposals arguably deliver on the former, but they do not deliver on the latter. Clarity and certainty are compatible with conservation and continuity, but do not on their own amount to replacement and reform. Moreover, most of the proposals would serve as instruments of government and as nominal constitutions. Fundamental questions, such as how to construct the unity of a people or how to serve the UK as a union state, are conspicuous by their absence. It is to these questions that I turn to next.

There is a near-universal understanding that, to be legitimate, the authority for a constitution must derive from the people of the state concerned—an understanding that stems from the anti-colonial movements in revolutionary North America and has subsequently migrated around the world. 82 However, not all proposals for a codified UK constitution are drafted in the name of ‘We the People’. 83 This is unsurprising: the role of an instrument of government is to clarify the rules and institutions under which ministers, civil servants and parliamentarians operate, not to wax lyrical about British values and the character of the British people. This stands in contrast to Thomas Paine’s dictum that ‘the constitution of a country is not the act of its government, but of the people constituting its government’. 84 The draft preambles by the IPPR in 1991, the LSE Institute of Public Affairs and Richard Gordon were drafted in the name of the people. 85 If the written constitution became the collective civic covenant of the British people, and not a simple reflection of the rules of government, what version of ‘popular sovereignty’ would authorise it? In this section, I discuss three commonly used ideal types of popular sovereignty ( patris , ethnos , demos ). 86 All of them are well-known, none of them were conceived in a context of universal suffrage and none of them are workable for the plurinational UK. This is also problematic for politicians who invoke the ‘will of the people’ as a mandate for policy choices. 87 There is a solution, but before I propose it, we need to clear away the assumptions about popular sovereignty.

The strongest conception of popular sovereignty amalgamates the democratic legitimacy of state power with the constituent power. We need to distinguish between the ‘populus’, or the population as such, and the political existence of a people. The strong conception presupposes an antecedent people that exists as a political unit prior to the constitution. That ancestral nation is patris (homeland). The state is not the result of the social contract, itself ‘an exercise of the imagination’, 88 but an actual entity with history, institutions, culture, language, ethics, an economy and art. It is held together, according to Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, not by force or fear, but by ‘the basic sense of order which everyone possesses’. 89 In other words, the general will manifests itself as concrete, social consensus. The people can write any constitution they want and retain a power to withdraw support and give themselves a new constitution at any time.

The strongest conception can be detected in political discourse, whether it is a ‘British Bill of Rights’, ‘British values’, ‘bringing rights back home’ or PM Theresa May’s interpretation of the 2016 referendum result as a decision by ‘the people of the United Kingdom’ to ‘restore, as we see it, our national self-determination’. 90 However, the construction of public ownership in this way does not work, given the size and ethnic composition of the UK population and the presence of different territorial identities. A range of people from different ethnic backgrounds live in England, Scotland, Wales and Northern Ireland. ‘Britain’ is at once a territorial and political unit that excludes Northern Ireland and an ‘imagined community’, 91 ie a socially constructed and psychologically represented social system in which ‘being British’ may be relevant and may be mobilised in some situations but not in others. 92 Patris is also undesirable and unnecessary. Its undesirability stems from its absolutist quality. Any measure sanctioned by the people would be valid on the ground that it articulates the homogeneous values and a shared identity. Popular sovereignty would be a like-for-like replacement for parliamentary sovereignty. In addition, a constitutional document is unnecessary for a substantively homogeneous people with shared values and a common identity. If the political unity of such a people is strong, then it does not require the assistance of a constitutional document (‘gentlemen do not need to put their word in writing, it is enough simply to give one’s word’ 93 ). If the political unity is weak, because the values and identity are diluted, then the fertile ground on which popular sovereignty flourishes is degraded, and the integrity of the people as patris , as an a priori decision-making unit, disappears.

The second ideal type of sovereignty contains no antecedent people and no prior right to political authority. For Jean-Jacques Rousseau, the creation of the constitution ex nihilo is a ‘civil act’. It requires prior deliberation and, crucially, unanimity. Majoritarian support is insufficient. The organising principle here is ethnos (nation). A legitimate political order requires an act of self-constitution by the people, which means that the minority must give their free consent if they are obliged to obey. 94 ‘Every man being born free and his own master, no one, under any pretext whatsoever, can make any man subject without his consent.’ 95 The constitution is, therefore, a pact of association (‘the act by which a people becomes a people’), 96 not a pact of submission (in which people elect leaders).

Although Rousseau was ‘the champion of popular sovereignty’, 97 his conception self-evidently does not apply to the UK. Advocates of codification are not proposing that the people authorise a new social order in a revolutionary moment. Moreover, Rousseau’s requirement for unanimity (and the death penalty for dissenters from the unanimous body) for the adoption and abrogation of a constitution is a non-starter. 98 His advocacy of a strict amendment formula and of the procedural entrenchment of fundamental laws is designed to ‘strengthen the constitution’ 99 and to prevent the popular sovereign from enacting a new constitution in the future. These requirements are difficult to reconcile with the codification debate in the UK.

In the third ideal type, popular sovereignty inheres in a constitutional framework of representative government, political equality and participation rights for the demos (people). For Immanuel Kant, consent by the governed is the only source of governmental legitimacy. But what kind of consent? According to Kant, actual consent by the people does not constitute a valid criterion for the substantive legitimacy or correctness of laws.

This is the test of the rightfulness of every public law. For if the law is such that a whole people could not possibly agree to it (for example, if it stated that a certain class of subjects must be privileged as a hereditary ruling class ), it is unjust; but if it is at least possible that a people could agree to it, it is our duty to consider the law as just, even if the people is at present in such a position or attitude of mind that it would probably refuse its consent if it were consulted. 100

Instead, it is the hypothetical will of a reasonable people that validates laws and guides lawmakers. But this creates a problem for democratic states: how can a political system call itself democratic in the absence of actual participation and consent from ‘the will of the entire people’, which is the only available strategy to legitimise governmental activity? Kant needs to marry hypothetical consent with an element of actual consent. Prior unanimous consent is, therefore, required for the principle of majoritarian decision making. Substantive unanimity is illusory—people will inevitably disagree on the substantive correctness of a decision. It is, therefore, imperative that all citizens unanimously consent to the principle of majoritarian decision making: ‘Thus the actual principle of being content with majority decisions must be accepted unanimously and embodied in a contract; and this itself must be the ultimate basis on which a constitution is established.’ 101

Kant does not discuss the people as a constitutive power, as in the other two versions of popular sovereignty, but as a constituted power. ‘A state ( civitas ) is a union of a multitude of men under laws of Right.’ 102 Within the lawfully constituted state, the legislative authority belongs ‘only to the united will of the people’, which, as the source of all rights, ‘ cannot do anyone wrong by its law’. 103 But the will of the people exhausts itself in the competences that are defined in the constitution. There is no antecedent people separated from the constitution, and the people do not enjoy a residual, sovereign power to overthrow the constitution at will. The idea that the people are the historical authors of the constitution is exposed as a myth, 104 and the legitimacy of collective decision making cannot be reduced either to the voluntariness of consent or to the reasonableness of an agreement.

For all its advances on the other two versions of sovereignty, it is not clear that the Kantian demos is a perfect match for the UK. The popular sovereign, the demos , is umbilically tied to the constitution, which means that the people cannot abrogate and replace their constitution while retaining their political existence and identity. 105 That does not sound like a winning formula for a people used to constitutional flexibility and unbridled freedom of action. Moreover, on every model of sovereignty, the discussion of ‘the people’ is complicated by conceptions of nationhood that are fixed. Patris , ethnos and demos each generate a stable image of ‘the people’, but with different interpretations in relation to general will, unanimity and majoritarianism.

But there is a more important reason for the complication. The revolutionary claim that all state power derives from the singular source of the people has a destabilising quality. The democratic principle ostensibly authorises the lawmaker not just to set up a constitution, but also to violate its own basic laws. Pure voluntarism puts paid to the notion of the constitutional state if whatever measure is enacted in the name of the people is law. The task of stabilising state power falls to disabling rules which, by placing strategic limits on governmental decision making, prevent a democracy from abolishing itself. 106 Stability, in turn, begets legitimacy, which constitutional regimes have acquired over time by withdrawing core competences from the voluntarism of a sovereign people and by anchoring the process of constitution making in the rationality of universal human rights. 107 In other words, the legitimacy of government stems from the dual commitment to the democratic self-determination of citizens and, as discussed above, to the articulation of individual rights into a comprehensive system of rights. Jürgen Habermas’s discourse theory harnesses the dual commitment to popular sovereignty and human rights, free consent and reasonable agreement, will and reason. It allows him to view the people as neither constitutive ( patris , ethnos ) nor constituted ( demos ), but as co-constitutive with a universal ideal of rights protection. 108 ‘What unites a nation of citizens as opposed to a Volksnation [ patris and ethnos ] is not some primordial substrate but rather an intersubjectively shared context of possible understanding.’ 109

The dialectical relationship between popular sovereignty (voluntarism) and human rights (rationalism) as sources of legitimacy is not discussed in any of the three conceptions that provide the deep context for constitution making and which have been discussed in this section. Nor is it expressed in any of the draft constitutional proposals for the UK. References to ‘We the People’ in the drafts are either formulaic or absent. Although all the draft constitutions now protect civil and political rights as a matter of course, which marks a change from previous generations when the case for rights needed to be made, 110 their inclusion is still cautious. The scope and degree of human rights protection never exceeds those provided by the European Convention on Human Rights. As discussed earlier, the Bill of Rights envisaged by the Joint Committee on Human Rights in 2008 would not have been entrenched and would not have allowed individuals to enforce economic and social rights against public authorities. This is acceptable for a constitution as an ‘instrument of government’. A ‘people’s constitution’, however, involves a symbiotic relationship between popular sovereignty and human rights, and not tentative references to an amorphous people and the lowest possible inclusion of civil and political rights as a compulsory accessory.

In addition to the dialectic between popular sovereignty and human rights, the present-day context of the UK creates its own dynamic relationship between the centre and the regions. That dynamic affects the criteria of statehood itself (government, population, territory), which, in turn, makes the UK an uneasy reference point for a single codified document. ‘Government’ is destabilised by the devolved regional legislatures and governments in Edinburgh, Cardiff and Belfast, which have ‘unsettled’ 111 the UK’s constitution. ‘Population’ searches for a demotic entity that is difficult to identify in a state with multiple designations, 112 four regions and six territorial identities (British, English, Irish, Northern Irish, Scottish and Welsh). ‘Territory’ is brought into question by the UK’s legal commitment to the possibility of Irish unification in section 1 of the Northern Ireland Act 1998, 113 as well as by the ongoing discussions about a second Scottish Independence referendum, 114 by a Labour-led Welsh government that refers to the UK as a ‘voluntary association of nations’ based on ‘popular sovereignty in each part of the UK’ 115 and by the presence of a nationalist party talking up the possibility of Welsh independence. 116 How should the constitution be drafted if the statehood criteria are less well defined than is usual? How can the process of codifying the constitution gain the support of the non-English regions and the loyalty of their populations? How can codification strengthen the Union?

According to conventional domestic constitutional interpretation, Parliament is the obvious body to write and ratify a constitution. It acts as the constituent assembly (it can ‘shift the basis of the constitution’) and as the legislative assembly (it enacts ordinary laws). 117 It is possible for legislatures more generally to become constituent assemblies for that purpose. 118 However, three recent interventions suggest that the constitution should not be written by Parliament. In 2012–13, the HCPCRC conducted an inquiry into the need for a UK-wide constitutional convention. The inquiry did not focus on a written constitution, which was the subject of a separate inquiry, 119 but examined the interaction between the increasingly devolved parts of the UK and considered the future constitutional structure of the UK. 120 In debating questions relating to the remit, composition and timing of the convention, the inquiry opened up extra-parliamentary avenues to discuss future constitutional change. The Chair of the Committee, Graham Allen MP, even introduced the Constitutional Convention Bill in the House of Commons, but it did not progress past first reading. 121

Two further interventions came from academics. Bruce Ackerman, writing before the pandemic of 2020, calculated that MPs would be ‘so overwhelmed with the challenges of managing Brexit over the next few years that they will have little time left for anything else’. 122 He, too, makes the case for a special Constitutional Convention, which should be elected by Parliament under ‘closed list proportional representation’, ‘debate the long-term, big picture issues’ and be given a reasonable deadline to draft a proposal to be put before the British people in a referendum. 123 Finally, Jeff King’s argument for a written constitution is premised on the position that ‘the people’s representatives should participate in the writing of the fundamental laws of the community’. 124 He proposes that the constitution be authored by a constituent assembly, ie a special-purpose body to draft a constitution. It should consist of citizens, electors and possibly residents; at any rate, ‘it must represent the people by being “representative, informed, and effective”’. 125

The problem with a UK-wide Convention is that it adopts a unitary conception of the British people. Although King is careful to dissociate his use of the people from patris and ethnos (‘a sovereign collective identity whose pronouncements for the people can persist over time’) and from demos (‘a distinct and unitary Will of the People determined by majoritarian voting procedures’), 126 he still views ‘those living in Britain’ 127 as a decision-making unit. While Ackerman acknowledges ‘dilemmas generated by Irish, Scottish, and Welsh demands for home rule’, his solution for ‘the British people’ (which consists in the creation of a new national holiday, Deliberation Day, to encourage voters to discuss the draft constitution a couple of weeks before it is put to them for approval in a special referendum) is distinctly unitary. 128

A UK-wide Convention assumes a pre-constitutional consensus on the identity of ‘the British people’ as well as shared normative commitments in relation to the state even if those commitments are implemented differently and asymmetrically in practice. No thought is given to a special role for Scotland, Wales and Northern Ireland in the constitution-making process or to their future status in a reconstituted UK. Arguing for a written constitution on the assumption of an ongoing commitment to the Union from the non-English regions represents a leap, and arguably even a lapse, of faith. Political discourse is already marked by policy divergence, by constitutional disagreement (Sewel Convention) and by strong regional parties, especially the Scottish National Party. Even a representative convention or assembly may not suffice to produce the societal consensus required for a stable outcome.

More importantly, the English doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty, which is still asserted as a Unionist principle, 129 now competes against a Celtic doctrine of popular sovereignty. The principle of consent migrated from the Northern Ireland context 130 to the opening provisions of the Scotland Act 2016 and the Wales Act 2017, which protect the respective regional parliament and government from being abolished ‘except on the basis of a decision of the people of Scotland [or Wales] voting in a referendum’. 131 This development raises questions for the legitimacy of constitution making. Would the written constitution derive its authority from a single community of citizens? Or would it represent the peoples of the non-English regions as sources of authority and subjects of legitimacy?

To repeat a point made earlier: to be legitimate, the constitution must derive from the original authority of a sovereign people. As a unitary concept, however, the category of the British people is cumbersome, dominated as it is by the size of the English population, which can always outvote the residents of Scotland, Wales and Northern Ireland. By way of contrast, European democracy theory has developed a new account of political community for the European Union called pouvoir constituant mixte . It is not intended as an abstract constituent power for an original founding moment, but as a rational reconstruction of the democratic character of the European Union, which consists of the citizens of the European Union and of the Member States. 132 For those reasons, pouvoir constituant mixte resonates in the UK as well. Every citizen participates in the democratic opinion and will-formation processes as a dual subject: as an individual British national and as a member of one of the four regions. 133 Additionally, the pouvoir constituant mixte honours a dialectic that is missing from patris , ethnos and demos . It saves the constituent power of the British people through disaggregation and then through reconstruction, allowing it to become not the presupposition, but the aspiration and normative reference point of the constitution. Whereas the unitary British people cannot reasonably be presupposed as the authors of a unitary constitution, the hybrid conception of pouvoir constituant mixte could legitimately serve as the basis for a constitutional debate.

Empirically, the relevance of the pouvoir constituant mixte for the UK is borne out. Many UK nationals are already comfortable with being members of two demoi at the same time. On the Moreno scale, 134 a majority of English participants identify as English (80%) and British (82%). 135 A majority of Scots identify as Scottish (84%) and as British (59%). 136 Just under half of people born in Wales identify either entirely as Welsh (21%) or more Welsh than British (27%), and a similar size identify either as equally Welsh and British (44%) or more British than Welsh (5%). 137 Pouvoir constituant mixte is of particular relevance in Northern Ireland, where the Belfast/Good Friday Agreement 1998 recognises ‘the birthright of all the people of Northern Ireland to identify themselves and be accepted as Irish or British, or both, as they may so choose’. 138 However, according to two recent and separate polls, fewer than half the people identify as predominantly British, 139 with the majority identifying as Irish, Northern Irish or European. 140

The possibility of disintegration and dissolution would shape the process of constitution making like the sword of Damocles. The cost of loyalty (integration, assimilation) is too high for the non-English regions, and the cost of exit (Irish unification, Scottish independence) is too high for the Unionist majority. Both options would increase polarisation, regionally as well as nationally. If the UK is to codify its constitution, it will need to accommodate the voice of the non-English regions with favourable terms and conditions. Unfavourable terms and conditions will force them to consider alternative options.

The literature on codification assumes the integrity of the UK, presupposes the constituent power of the British people and takes the loyalty of the non-English regions for granted. The draft constitutional proposals codify the existing devolution settlement, but they do not seize the moment to reimagine the UK. Since Northern Ireland and Scotland have potential exit routes, their voice in the process of constitution making and operations of state building requires special attention. With the Wales Act 2017, Wales drew level with Scotland in terms of devolved governance arrangements, so it should enjoy parity of status even without a credible exit strategy. It would be a missed opportunity if the codification process preserved a random constitutional moment in time, rather than considered ways of strengthening the Union, like federalism, regional autonomy and pouvoir constituant mixte . In the long run, the famously flexible UK constitution will need to morph into an ‘incompletely theorised agreement’ with multilateral, rapid and dynamic response mechanisms to deal with unpredictable changes, not hold fast to centrality, clarity, certainty, rigidity and finality.

While I have expressed here my concerns about the desirability of codifying the existing UK constitution, I have at the same time offered no defence of the institutions, conventions and practices of the unwritten constitution. I am, therefore, not convinced by the attempts to convert the unwritten constitution into a written one. Nor am I against codification as a matter of principle. I am simply not persuaded by the suitability of the globally dominant paradigm of liberal ‘AngloEurocentric constitutionalism’. 141 The clarity and certainty of the monolithic constitution do not suit the eclectic power structures or the multiregional, plurinational and evolving nature of the UK.

One thing is certain: a constitution that consciously tries to square the circle between the centralised state apparatus and the cleavages wrought by the territorial constitution and the politics of policy divergence would have to be written. To do so, the drafters of an accommodationist constitution would need to study the literature on conflict resolution, power-sharing and consociational techniques rather than the canon of rational, liberal, nation-state constitutions. The accommodationist state would contain multiple public identities and provide for a form of constitutional pluralism that ‘acknowledge[s] the legitimacy of every other [normative order] within its own sphere, while none asserts or acknowledges constitutional superiority over another’. 142 Accommodation requires provisional solutions, ambiguity, incremental strategies, deferral mechanisms and alternative institutional arrangements that can manage inconsistency as part of a strategy of coexistence. 143 Such an approach builds capacity for a constitutional dialectic that consists of mutual construction, ambivalent relations and opposing dynamics which, as I have shown, exist in relation to government, the people and the territorial constitution.

Instead of educating citizens, the process would be a steep learning curve for the legal experts and political representatives charged with drafting the constitution. Instead of clarifying the existing UK constitution (all the attempts show that it can be done for an essentially unitary state), a collective effort is required to reimagine and redefine the UK as a state for which there is no precedent or template. For these reasons, the UK should not adopt one of the proposed written constitutions. It should be reconstituted.

AC Grayling, ‘Why the UK Needs a Written Constitution’ in DJ Galligan (ed), Constitution in Crisis: The New Putney Debates (IB Tauris 2017).

Galligan (n 1).

Andrew Blick and Peter Hennessy, ‘Brexit and the Melting of the British Constitution’ (The Constitution Society 2019).

Cass R Sunstein, ‘Incompletely Theorized Agreements’ (1995) 108 Harv L Rev 1733.

Richard Gordon, Repairing British Politics: A Blueprint for Constitutional Change (Hart Publishing 2010); Elliot Bulmer, ‘Do We Need a Written Constitution’, debate between Elliot Bulmer and Paul Bickley (Theos Think Tank, 24 October 2019): ‘We need a restored civic covenant to bind ourselves together as a political community under common rules for the common good.’

Daniel Elazar, ‘Constitution-Making: The Pre-eminently Political Act’ in KG Banting and R Simeon (eds), Redesigning the State: The Politics of Constitutional Change in Industrial Nations (Macmillan 1985) 233.

Sotirios A Barber, Constitutional Failure (University Press of Kansas 2014) xvii: ‘constitutional reform must therefore be nothing short of cultural reform’.

R (Jackson) v Attorney General [2005] UKHL 56, [2005] 1 AC 262 [104]; also [107] (Lord Hope), [102] (Lord Steyn), [159] (Lady Hale). See also Axa General Insurance Ltd and Others v The Lord Advocate [2011] UKSC 46, [2012] AC 868.

The UK Withdrawal from the European Union (Legal Continuity) (Scotland) Bill [2018] UKSC 64, [2019] AC 1022 [41].

Martin Loughlin and Stephen Tierney, ‘The Shibboleth of Sovereignty’ (2018) 81 MLR 986, 1015–16.

Brendan O’Leary, ‘The Character of the 1998 Agreement: Results and Prospects’ in R. Wilford (ed), Aspects of the Belfast Agreement (OUP 2001) 66.

Edmund Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France (first published 1790, Dent 1910).

Michael Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics (Methuen 1962).

From JAG Griffith, ‘The Political Constitution’ (1979) 42 MLR 1 to < https://judicialpowerproject.org.uk/> .

The House of Commons Political and Constitutional Reform Committee, A New Magna Carta? (HC 2014–15, 463) 24.

Roger Scruton, A Political Philosophy (Continuum 2006) vii–viii.

Vernon Bogdanor, The New British Constitution (Hart Publishing 2009) ix.

Home Office, Rights Brought Home: The Human Rights Bill (Cm 3782, 1997).

Roger Masterman, The Separation of Powers in the Contemporary Constitution (CUP 2011).

J Baker, ‘The Unwritten Constitution of the United Kingdom’ (2013) 15 Ecclesiastical Law Journal 4, 10.

Earlier proposals for a written constitution are limited to Jeremy Bentham, Constitutional Code , vol I (F Rosen and JH Burns ed, first published 1830, Clarendon Press 1983).

Lord Hailsham, ‘Elective Dictatorship’, Richard Dimbleby Lecture (BBC 1976); Lord Hailsham, The Dilemma of Democracy: Diagnosis and Prescription (Collins 1978). Lord Hailsham did not pursue this project as Lord Chancellor (1979–87), and by 1991 was defending the flexibility of the unwritten constitution: Ferdinand Mount, The British Constitution Now: Recovery or Decline? (Heinemann 1992) 3.

Leslie Scarman, English Law—The New Dimension , Hamlyn Lectures (Stevens & Sons 1974); Lord Scarman, ‘The Shape of Things to Come’: The Shape and Future Law and Constitution of the United Kingdom , Radcliffe Lectures (University of Warwick 1989); Leslie Scarman, Why Britain Needs a Written Constitution , Fourth Sovereignty Lecture (Charter 88 Trust 1992).

Gordon Brown, Constitutional Change and the Future of Britain , First Sovereignty Lecture (Charter 88 Trust 1992).

HC Deb 10 June 2009, col 798; Labour Party Manifesto 2010, which pledged to create ‘an All Party Commission to chart a course towards a Written Constitution’ (para 9:3).

IPPR, A Written Constitution for the United Kingdom (Mansell 1991).

Tony Benn and Andrew Hood, Common Sense: New Constitution for Britain (Hutchinson 1993).

Vernon Bogdanor, Tarunabh Khaitan and Stefan Vogenauer, ‘Should Britain Have A Written Constitution?’ (2007) 78 Political Quarterly 499.

Gordon (n 5).

Stephen Hockman and others, ‘Towards a Codified Constitution’ (2010) 7(1) Justice.

Robert Blackburn, ‘Enacting a Written Constitution for the United Kingdom’ (2015) 36 Stat LR 1; Andrew. Blick, Beyond Magna Carta: A Constitution for the United Kingdom (Hart Publishing 2015).

HCPCRC (n 15).

< http://lsedesignunit.com/theconstitution/offline/download.pdf > accessed 31 July 2020.

Lady Hale, ‘The UK Constitution on the Move’, The Canadian Institute for Advanced Legal Studies’ Cambridge Lectures (7 July 2017). In his fifth 2019 Reith Lecture called ‘Shifting the Foundations’, former UK Supreme Court Justice Jonathan Sumption argued against the UK adopting a written constitution: J Sumption, Trials of the State: Law and the Decline of Politics (Profile Books 2019).

‘Do We Need a Written Constitution?’, debate between Prof Sionaidh Douglas-Scott and Prof Nick Barber at the Constitution Unit, UCL, 28 November 2019; S Douglas-Scott and A Tomkins, ‘Does Britain Need a Proper Constitution?’ Prospect Magazine (2 April 2019); ‘Do We Need A Written Constitution’ (n 5).

BBC Radio 4, ‘Britain’s Constitutional Dilemma: Who Now Runs the Country?’ (26 September 2019); Channel 4, ‘Does Britain Need a Written Constitution after Brexit?’ (29 October 2019).

From ‘Britain’s Unwritten Constitution Suddenly Looks Fragile’ New York Times (31 August 2019) to ‘Britain Doesn’t Need a Written Constitution’ GQ Magazine (20 February 2020).

In August 2020, the Scottish Fabians, a centre-left think tank, proposed a new Act of Union, with the aim of codifying ‘a stable constitutional framework for the UK’ < http://scottish.fabians.org.uk/a-new-act-of-the-union > accessed November 2020. In February 2021, a report commissioned by the Labour Party, ‘Remaking the British State: For the Many Not the Few’ (Leader of the Opposition’s Office 2021) argued for a codified constitution as the new supreme law that would limit the law-making powers of Parliament and empower the courts to strike down unconstitutional legislation.

Bruce Ackerman, ‘Why Britain Needs a Written Constitution—and Can’t Wait for Parliament to Write One’ (2018) 89 Political Quarterly 584; Jeff King, ‘The Democratic Case for a Written Constitution’ [2019] CLP 1; Vernon Bogdanor, Beyond Brexit: Towards a British Constitution (IB Tauris 2019); B Dickson, Writing the United Kingdom Constitution (Manchester University Press 2019); Brian Christopher Jones, Constitutional Idolatry and Democracy: Challenging the Infatuation with Writtenness (Edward Elgar 2020).

Noted by R Hazell, ‘Do We Need a Written Constitution?’, debate at the Constitution Unit, UCL (28 November 2019).

Heinz Klug, ‘Constitution Making and Social Transformation’ in D Landau and H Lerner (eds), Comparative Constitution Making (Edward Elgar 2019) 47.

Giovanni Sartori, ‘Constitutionalism: A Preliminary Discussion’ (1962) 56 American Political Science Review 853, 855.

House of Lords Constitution Committee, Reviewing the Constitution: Terms of Reference and Method of Working (HL 2001–02, 11) para 20.

The HCPCRC Written Constitution (n 15) confirms Parliament’s exclusive powers to legislate ‘without limitation’ on all matters, including the Constitution (art 17). The Oxford student draft constitution (n 28) also preserves supremacy (at 502). The situation is unclear in the IPPR Constitution (n 26): on the one hand, ‘any law… that is inconsistent with this Constitution ceases to have effect to the extent of the inconsistency’ (art 1(4)), but on the other ,‘Parliament has exclusive powers to make laws with respect to … the Constitution’ (art 53.1). Gordon (n 5) would subject parliamentary legislation to the Constitution (art 11). Article 7.7 of the LSE’s Constitution (n 33) grants courts the power of constitutional review: ‘In the case of conflicts between the wording of this Constitution and ordinary statutes, the Constitution shall have precedence and prevail.’

HCPCRC (n 15) 284.

Jon Elster, ‘Forces and Mechanisms in the Constitution-Making Process’ (1995) 45 Duke LJ 364.

Klug (n 41) 48–9.

IPPR (n 26) 9.

Gordon (n 5) 6.

Blackburn (n 31) 5. Professor Blackburn was the lead author of the HCPCRC’s three constitutional models.

IPPR (n 26) 10.

Gordon (n 5) 7.

Elazar (n 6).

Blackburn (n 31) 4.

Ipsos Mori, ‘Audit of Political Engagement 5: The 2008 Report with a Special Focus on the Constitution’ (Hansard Society 2008).

YouGov/Unlock Democracy Survey Results, 15–16 November 2018.

ComRes/Daily Express poll on 4 December 2018.

House of Commons Political and Constitutional Reform Committee, A New Magna Carta? (HC 2014–15, 599) 21.

Sartori (n 42) 861.

< www.constituteproject.org/constitution/United_Kingdom_2013.pdf >.

James Melton, Christine Stuart and Daniel Helen, ‘To Codify or Not to codify? Lessons from Consolidating the United Kingdom’s Constitutional Statutes’ (The Constitution Unit, UCL, March 2015) 4.

HCPCRC (n 15) 19.

HCPCRC (n 59) 17.

Sartori (n 42) 855.

ibid 854. See also The Federalist Papers No 47.

Stephen Holmes, Passions and Constraint: On the Theory of Liberal Democracy (University of Chicago Press 1995) 5–7, 161–4; John Searle, Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language (CUP 1997) 33–6.

Niklas Luhmann, Law as a Social System (KA Ziegert tr, OUP 2004) 410.

The Governance of Britain (Cm 7170, 2007) paras 204–10.

Commission on a Bill of Rights, ‘Do We Need a UK Bill of Rights’ (August 2011) para 26; see also the speech by the then Lord Chancellor and Secretary of State for Justice, Jack Straw, ‘Towards a Bill of Rights and Responsibilities’ (21 January 2008).

The Governance of Britain (n 69) para 210.

HC and HL Joint Committee on Human Rights, A Bill of Rights for the UK? (2007–08, HL 165–I, HC 150–I) 235.

ibid 52–3; see also IPPR (n 26) art 27.

The Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 1948.

PM Gordon Brown speech at Liberty (25 October 2007).

Jürgen Habermas, ‘Kant’s Idea of Perpetual Peace: At Two Hundred Years’ Historical Remove’ in C Cronin and P De Greiff (eds), The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory (MIT Press 1998) 191.

HC and HL Joint Committee on Human Rights (n 72) para 34. See further TM Scanlon, ‘Rights, Goals and Fairness’ in J Waldron (ed), Theories of Rights (OUP 1984) 137–52.

Jürgen Habermas, ‘Constitutional Democracy: A Paradoxical Union of Contradictory Principles?’ (2001) 29 Political Theory 766, 779.

ibid 767, 779.

Blick (n 31) 289.

K Marx, ‘The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte’ in D Fernbach (ed), Surveys from Exile: Political Writings , vol 2 (Penguin Books 1973) 146.

Tom Ginsburg, Daniel Rockmore and Nick Foti, ‘We the Peoples: The Global Origins of Constitutional Preambles’ (2014) 46 George Washington International Law Review 101.

Although the HCPCRC (n 15) para14 recommends that the constitution ‘should belong to the people of the United Kingdom’, none of the three models contain a reference to popular sovereignty. Nor does the draft constitution in Bogdanor, Khaitan and Vogenauer (n 28) 506.

Thomas Paine, The Rights of Man (first published 1791, Viking Penguin 1984) 71.

IPPR (n 26) Preamble; LSE Institute of Public Affairs, The Constitution (2015) (n 33): ‘We the people of all the nations in the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland being joined together in common purpose and in mutual respect, hereby affirm the permanent living principles of our democracy and the rights and responsibilities of all persons therein’. See also Gordon (n 5) 45: clause 2 provides that ‘National sovereignty shall vest in the people, who shall exercise that sovereignty through delegation of the powers as set out in this Constitution to their representatives and through the other provisions of this Constitution’.

I develop the outline provided in Lars Vinx, ‘The Incoherence of Strong Popular Sovereignty’ (2013) 11 ICON 101, 102–3.

Albert Weale, The Will of the People: A Modern Myth (Polity Press 2018).

Martin Loughlin and Neil Walker, ‘Introduction’ in Loughlin and Walker (eds), The Paradox of Constitutionalism: Constituent Power and Constitutional Form (OUP 2007) 2.

GWF Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right (CUP 1991) § 268.

Prime Minister’s letter to Donald Tusk triggering Article 50, 29 March 2017 < www.gov.uk/government/publications/prime-ministers-letter-to-donald-tusk-triggering-article-50 >.

Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism (Verso 2006).

See generally ‘Citizenship and Belonging: What Is Britishness?’ (Commission for Racial Equality, 2005).

Peter Goodrich and Yifat Hachamovitch, ‘Time Out of Mind: An Introduction to the Semiotics of Common Law’ in P Fitzpatrick (ed), Dangerous Supplements: Resistance and Renewal in Jurisprudence (Pluto 1991) 168.

Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract (first published 1762, Penguin 1968) Book I, ch 5.

ibid Book IV, ch 2.

ibid Book I, ch 5.

David Rosenfeld, ‘Rousseau’s Unanimous Contract and the Doctrine of Popular Sovereignty’ (1987) 8 History of Political Thought 83.

Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Political Writings. Containing the Social Contract, Considerations on the Government of Poland, Constitutional Project for Corsica, Part I . (University of Wisconsin Press 1986) 215; Melissa Schwartzberg, ‘Rousseau on Fundamental Law’ (2003) 51 Political Studies 387.

Rousseau, (n 98) 215.

Immanuel Kant, ‘On the Common Saying: “This May be True in Theory, but It Does Not Apply in Practice”’ in Kant: Political Writings , 2nd edn (first published 1793, CUP 1991) 79.

ibid 77, 79.

Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals (CUP 1991) para 45.

ibid para 46.

Hans Kelsen, Vom Wesen und Wert der Demokratie (Mohr 1920) 14–25.

Vinx (n 86) 103.

Norberto Bobbio, The Future of Democracy (Polity Press 1987) 65.

Chris Thornhill, ‘Constitution Making and Constitutionalism in Europe’ in Landau and Lerner (n 41) 445; Chris Thornhill, ‘On Misunderstanding States: The Transnational Constitution in the National Constitution’ (2018) 16 ICON 1186, 1194.

Habermas, ‘Constitutional Democracy’ (n 78) 767; Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy (MIT Press 1996) 121–2.

Jürgen Habermas, ‘Remark’s on Dieter Grimm’s “Does Europe Need a Constitution?”’ in P Gowan and P Anderson (eds), The Question of Europe (Verso 1997) 262.

Michael Zander, A Bill of Rights? (Sweet & Maxwell 1975); RM Dworkin, A Bill of Rights for Britain: Why British Liberty Needs Protection (Chatto & Windus 1990).

Neil Walker, ‘Our Constitutional Unsettlement’ [2014] PL 529.

George Orwell, ‘England, Your England’ Selected Essays (Penguin Books 1957) 72: ‘we call our islands by no less than six different names, England, Britain, Great Britain, the British Isles, the United Kingdom and, in very exalted moments, Albion’.

Under this provision, Northern Ireland remains part of the UK unless and until ‘a majority of the people of Northern Ireland voting in a poll’ express a wish to form part of a united Ireland. See also Belfast Agreement, 10 April 1998, art 1(ii); HM Government, New Withdrawal Agreement and Political Declaration (19 October 2019); Ireland/Northern Ireland Protocol, art 1(1). In January 2021, a poll by LucidTalk for the Sunday Times found that a majority (51%) of those surveyed in Northern Ireland would support a referendum in the next five years. The same poll found that 47% were in favour of remaining part of the UK, with 42% in favour of a united Ireland, which falls short of the criterion in s 1 of the Northern Ireland Act 1998.

The Scottish National Party’s 2019 General Election manifesto stated the party’s intention to hold a second independence referendum. Having won a majority of Scotland’s seats, First Minister Nicola Sturgeon claimed to have a ‘cast-iron mandate’. To that end, she sent an official request to the Prime Minister in December 2019 which was rejected in January 2020.

Welsh Government, Reforming Our Union: Shared Governance in the UK (2019) Proposition 1.

‘Welsh Independence Referendum “Before 2030” Plaid Leader Says’ ( BBC Online , 4 October 2019). According to the Savanta ComRes/ITV Welsh Barometer Poll in March 2021, support for Welsh independence has gradually increased to 39% of those surveyed—the highest level of support for Welsh independence ever recorded. A clear majority (55%) supports further devolution of powers to the Welsh Parliament: ICM Unlimited/BBC Wales—St David’s Day Poll 2020. See also the non-party campaign for independence < www.yes.cymru >, whose membership jumped from 2000 in early 2020 to over 17,000 in early 2021: BBC News, ‘Yes Cymru: Independence “Not Possible” Without Political Change’ (17 January 2021).

AV Dicey, Introduction to the Study of the Law of the Constitution (10th edn, Macmillan 1959) 37. See also the critique in A de Tocqueville, Democracy in America (Sever & Francis 1863) 126: ‘In England, the constitution may change continually; or rather, it does not in reality exist; the Parliament is at once a legislative and a constituent assembly.’

Jon Elster, ‘Legislatures as Constituent Assemblies’ in RW Bauman and T Kahana (eds), The Least Examined Branch: The Role of Legislatures in the Constitutional State (CUP 2006).

House of Commons Political and Constitutional Reform Committee, Do We Need a Constitutional Convention for the UK? (HC 2012–13, 371).

< https://services.parliament.uk/bills/2015-16/constitutionalconventionno2.html> accessed in August 2020.

Ackerman (n 39) 588.

King (n 39) 5.

Ackerman (n 39) 584, 588–9.

See s 28(7) of the Scotland Act, s 107(5) of the Government of Wales Act 2006 and s 5(6) of the Northern Ireland Act 1998.

Article 1 of the Belfast/Good Friday Agreement 1998 states that the right of self-determination for ‘the people of the island of Ireland alone’ is to be exercised ‘on the basis of consent’. The Northern Ireland Act 1998, s 1 states that Northern Ireland ‘shall not cease’ in its entirety to be part of the UK ‘without the consent of a majority of the people of Northern Ireland voting in a poll held for the purposes’.

Scotland Act 2016, s 1; Wales Act 2017, s 1.

Vlad Constantinesco, ‘L’Union européene: par le droi ou vers le politique? (ad augusta per augusta?)’ in G Duprat (ed), L’Union européene, droit, politique, démocratie (Presses universitaires de France 1996) 186; Jürgen Habermas, The Crisis of the European Union: A Response (Polity Press 2012) 28–37; Markus Patberg, ‘Introduction: The EU’s Pouvoir Constituant Mixte—Exploring the Systematic Potential of an Innovative Category’ (2017) 55 JCMS 165, and articles by Habermas, Peter Niesen, Jelena von Achenbach, Markus Patberg and Klaus Günther in the same issue.

Habermas, The Crisis of the European Union (n 132) 37.

L Moreno, ‘Scotland, Catalonia, Europeanization and the “Moreno Question’” (2006) 54 Scottish Affairs 1.

YouGov/BBC English Identity Survey Results, March 2018.

YouGov/BBC Attitudes to Scottishness Survey Results, April 2018.

ICM Unlimited/BBC Wales—St David’s Day Poll 2019.

Agreement between the Government of the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland and the Government of Ireland, 10 April 1998, art 1(iv).

45% in the Northern Ireland Life and Times Survey, Political Attitudes, 2019; 47% in the LucidTalk/YouGov/BBC, Northern Ireland Tracker Poll, May 2018.

See further Kevin McNicholl, Clifford Stevenson and John Garry, ‘How the “Northern Irish” National Identity Is Understood and Used by Young People and Politicians’ (2019) 40 Political Psychology 487.

Günter Frankenberg, ‘Constitutions as Commodities: Notes on a Theory of Transfer’ (2013) 4 Comparative Law Review 1, 2.

Neil MacCormick, Questioning Sovereignty (OUP 1999) 104.

Hanna Lerner and Asli Ü Bali, ‘Constitutional Design without Constitutional Moments: Lessons from Religiously Divided Societies’ (2016) 49 Cornell Int’l LJ 227, 306.

Author notes

Email alerts, citing articles via.

  • Recommend to your Library

Affiliations

  • Online ISSN 1464-3820
  • Print ISSN 0143-6503
  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Institutional account management
  • Rights and permissions
  • Get help with access
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

Should the UK Adopt a Codified Constitution?

Arguments in favour include:

  • It would provide clear rules, with less confusion as to what the constitution means
  • It would formally limit the powers of government, addressing the problem of elective dictatorship
  • It could be policed and protected by judges, who are politically independent and neutral
  • It would allow for a stronger protection of rights, as rights would be fully entrenched and more difficult to set aside
  • It would strengthen citizenship, giving people a clear idea of not only their rights but the purpose and workings of the political system. It could also be a source of unity for the nation
  • It would bring the UK into line with other modern democracies

Arguments against include:

  • It would be too difficult to change and may become outdated
  • It would give unelected judges to power to prevent elected government from carrying out its pledges
  • Uncodified constitutions are organic and naturally evolving, codified constitutions are more ‘legalistic’ and arbitrarily implemented
  • A codified constitution may be unnecessary- government power could be checked by strengthening the existing systems
  • It may be harder for a government to get things done and fulfil its manifesto promises

Should the UK adopt a fully entrenched bill of rights?

  • It would make the government more subject to the law, as rights will be ‘higher’ than other laws. This will make the government more responsible and accountable
  • Civil liberties would be better guaranteed and protected- they wouldn’t be set aside under any circumstance
  • It would make people more aware of their rights, so has educational benefits
  • There is already an agreement on rights (through the European Convention and Human Rights Act), so implementing a fully entrenched bill of rights would not be controversial
  • Judges become more powerful and influential, meaning they end up making law- and they are unelected and socially unrepresentative
  • Judges may become politicised and lose their independence, as they are more involved in the policy process
  • Raising awareness of rights may come at the expense of awareness of responsibilities. Individual rights may supersede the rights of the community
  • Rights are artificial constructs which may be difficult to implement in ‘the real world’

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

To codify or not to codify the UK constitution? Advantages and disadvantages of codified constitutions

Profile image of Karolina Niemiec

A constitution is an aggregate of fundamental principles that are essential for an organization of state. The British constitution is only one of the few nations in the world that do not have a written constitution. There are various reasons why that may be the case, including a lack of critical moment in history such as independence or freedom from an old regime (as it was the case in France or Germany). The fact that only few other countries are in the same position as UK as well as a very important 800th anniversary of Magna Carta in 2015 have rekindled the debate on whether the UK should retain its uncodified constitution or whether they should follow other countries and produce a written constitution. This dissertation will firstly explain how the British constitution actually works, what are the main principles of it and why it is the way it is. It will then introduce some of the arguments in favour of codification that had been brought forward as well as arguments against it. Furthermore, it will address difficulties that would result from the codification. The early research suggests that codification of the constitution would result increased accountability, balance, stability and clarity making it highly desirable. However, the current Westminster system (i.e. uncodified constitution) already holds all of these positive aspects. UK’s unwritten constitution proved to be successful over the years. It produced a stable government in terms of democracy, transparency and human rights. Its flexibility allowed the state to adapt to constantly changing society and take care of its citizens. This flexibility would be lost if the constitution was to be codified. Moreover, codification of the constitution would bring some practical difficulties including the scope of the constitution or finding enough funds to cover the costs. The practical difficulties that would be caused by the codification outweigh the advantage of making the constitution clearer and easier to access for the public. Thus, the research of this dissertation finds that the UK should not codify its constitution.

Related Papers

Ahmet Emrah Geçer

Notwithstanding “Magna Carta Libertatum”, which is accepted the first constitutional document in the history, was issued by King John of England, the United Kingdom has not adopted a codified constitution until now. In 2015, the United Kingdom celebrated 800th anniversary of Magna Carta. However, the debate continues on whether or not the UK Constitution should be codified. In this study, legal opinions of distinguished jurists regarding the issue will be briefly analysed.

should the uk codify its constitution essay

Daniel M A S T E R T O N Doig

This paper critically evaluates the case for constitutional modernisation in the UK.

waqas waqas

Andrew Blick

Connie Rwankote

The Northern Ireland legal quarterly

Brice Dickson

Toby McKinnon

Certain areas of English public law remain interestingly under-examined. Indeed, comparative approaches based on the distinction between common and civil law are scarce. I am interested in examining the implications of the absence of a common-law concept of the 'state' in British public law and in comparing this jurisprudentially ascertainable but peculiar fact to our near European neighbours, the jurisdictions of which are usually marked by elaborate administrative 'secondary' legal systems. This state-basd approach, expounded by Tomkins, might explain some of the peculiarities of our public law, e.g. what is the interrelationship of codification and civil liberties? The influence of codification is felt not only in private law.

Chris Clarke

Cristina Parau

ermanno calzolaio

This essay aims at reflecting on the persistent relevance of the traditional distinction between ‘written’ and ‘unwritten’ law as an essential feature of the English legal tradition, in order to better understand the current discussion concerning the enactment of a written Constitution for the United Kingdom, after the wide public consultation launched in 2014 by House of Commons. Three main aspects are considered: the difference between the idea of Rule of law and the continental idea of Staatsrecht, the concept of parliamentary sovereignty, the relationship between statute law and case law. It will be argued that even if a written constitution should ever see the light in the United Kingdom, it will presumably have a very particular status. A peculiarly ‘British’ one. Ermanno Calzolaio*

RELATED PAPERS

Prashant Jani

Media & viestintä

Maria Kaisa Aula

… Business & Economics …

Vlado Dimovski

Alice Quiocho

Toplum ve Sosyal Hizmet

Melike Yavaş , Erhan Elmaoglu

Research in Microbiology

Emmy De Buck

Revista Medica Electronica

Maritza Isabel Martinez Silva

RUDI RUHARDI

Renato Balbim

dominique couret

Marco Lucato

Computational Geometry

Saeed Mehrabi

ELECTROPHORESIS

Victor Gonzalez

Journal of Neurology, Neurosurgery &amp; Psychiatry

Askar Ghorbani

Nestor Compaore

The Innovation of Social Studies Journal

Herry Putro

Physical Review Letters

joseph milana

Dina Destari

Journal of Pain and Symptom Management

Sébastien Simard

Economics Letters

Wesley Holliday

New Journal of Physics

Ines Mariño

Applied Rheology

Manfred Wilhelm

Indonesian Journal of Electrical Engineering and Computer Science

Rajashree Shettar

Norba. Revista de Historia - NRH

Carmen Aranegui Gascó

Henry Sacks

RELATED TOPICS

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

should the uk codify its constitution essay

To Codify or Not To Codify? Lessons from Consolidating the United Kingdom’s Constitutional Statutes

• Only a few countries in the world lack a codified constitution. The UK is one of those countries. This has prompted some to advocate for the codification of the UK’s constitution. Perhaps the most notable proponents of such a position, at least recently, are the members of the Political and Constitutional Reform Committee (PCRC), but they are certainly not the only actors to champion this position.

• This report contributes to the debate over codification of the UK’s constitution by comparing the contents of the existing written elements of the UK’s constitution to other countries’ constitutional texts. In doing so, we are able to identify, with great precision, the topics addressed in other countries’ constitutions but omitted from constitutionally relevant statutes in the UK. Reflecting on the topics ‘missing’ from the UK’s constitution offers three lessons for those contemplating further codification of the UK’s constitution:

1. Much of the UK’s constitutional order is already written down in statute form.

2. Many details about the executive, the legislature and the relationship between these two branches of government are regulated entirely by convention. These are the parts of the UK’s constitution that are most vulnerable to conflicting interpretations and should be prioritised if more of the UK’s constitution is codified.

3. Further codification is not essential. Much of what is uncodified has recently been incorporated into the Cabinet Manual and other texts. In addition, the parts of the UK’s constitution that remain uncodified are also the parts of the constitutional order where conventions are the most well-established. As a result, codifying these elements would likely have minimal impact on day-to-day politics.

Get the latest updates

Comments/​questions.

Hodder Education Magazines logo

Politics Review

Does the UK need a codified constitution?

should the uk codify its constitution essay

Karl Marx’s theory of history

An evaluation of the latest developments in the debate over whether the UK should codify its constitution

  • Volume 31, 2021/ 2022
  • Constitution (and devolution)
  • Judiciary and European Union and Relations between the branches
  • UK Politics

Nick Gallop

should the uk codify its constitution essay

All major exam boards require a full understanding of constitutional changes since 1997. In addition, the AQA specification references ‘issues and debates around recent constitutional changes’ and Edexcel asks whether the UK should change to adopt an ‘entrenched and codified’ constitution.

For many legal theorists and political commentators, the constitutional arrangements that currently exist in the UK are not fit for purpose. The country’s protracted and acrimonious withdrawal from the EU, its disjointed response to the Covid-19 crisis and the growth of nationalist forces within the union itself appear to have exposed governing arrangements that are in urgent need of reform:

Your organisation does not have access to this article.

Sign up today to give your students the edge they need to achieve their best grades with subject expertise

Related articles:

should the uk codify its constitution essay

Nationalism

should the uk codify its constitution essay

A return to hard power?

should the uk codify its constitution essay

Anthony Giddens

should the uk codify its constitution essay

UK party conferences in 2023

Uncodified Constitution of the United Kingdom Essay

Introduction, the definition of a constitution, the existing constitution of the uk, should the constitution be codified.

It is quite a complicated question whether the UK really has a constitution in its modern sense. Back in the 18th century it was not even a question; the British constitution was recognized and celebrated for its democratic spirit, particularly by French Enlighteners and some of the American Founding Fathers. But since the Americans have decided to write down their principles of government into a document and to call it “Constitution,” and a lot of other countries, such as the newly-freed Latin American colonies, followed their example, the term “constitution” is mostly associated with a document. As the UK does not have a single document of such a kind, it is sometimes claimed that the country does not have a constitution at all.

First of all, the definition of a constitution is not merely “a document containing the principles of government,” as some consider. Constitution is principles of government as they are, written down or not. To be a constitution, these principles must determine the relationship between different governmental institutions, as well as between government and people, and people’s rights and freedoms. A careful study of the sources of the UK principles of government reveals that all the three mentioned issues are covered by these sources. Political activists in the UK keep making suggestions to codify the constitution, but in each case their suggestions contain an offer to alter it, and only then codify. To my opinion, the processes of amendment and codification should not be mixed.

Hence, the UK has a constitution, even though it is not codified, and the requirements to codify it has nothing to do with its validity as an acting constitution.

The first step to find out whether the UK has a constitution is to determine what exactly constitution is. According to Oxford Dictionary of law, “constitution” is defined as “the rules and practices that determine the composition and functions of the organs of central and local government in a state and regulate the relationship between the individual and the state” (Martin, 2003, p. 108). The dictionary entry further mentions that the majority of the countries dispose of a written document as their constitution. One of the main properties of such a disposal is a possibility to alter a constitution through a special procedure, whereas no such procedures are needed to change the statutes, of which the UK constitution partly consist. However, it also consists of common law rules and constitutional conventions (Martin, 2003, p. 108), which are hard or impossible to amend.

Constitution establishes principles that dictate who is allowed to make laws and how, what should be the relations between the main institutions of government, what are the rights and freedoms of citizens and how those are protected and guaranteed (Elliott & Quinn, 2007, p. 1). In general, the term “constitution” refers to the set of rules, according to which a government operates, rather than to a document. In case if those rules are not written or codified (i.e. collected in a single document), they are still defined as a constitution.

Anthony King distinguishes two types: constitutions and Constitutions. The first ones, he states, are never written down; they are the rules of the relationship between parts of government and government and people. Constitutions with the capital “C” are documents, in which constitutions are recorded. These two types overlap but do not coincide (King, 2011, p. 3-4).

The next question that needs to be answered is whether the active governmental rules of the UK, which we consider our constitution, actually qualify as a constitution. For that purpose, we need to examine the current constitution of the UK.

The UK constitution can be summed up in the following central principle: the Parliament makes (or abolishes) laws with the power of the Crown, and these laws cannot be challenged. Other principles include the separation of powers and the rule of law.

The sources of the UK constitution are the following. First, statute law, which is the body of the Acts of Parliament. The Acts are considered the highest source of law due to the principle of parliamentary sovereignty. Some particular statutes are of special importance. Among them are: the Petition of Right (1628), the Bill of Rights (1689), the Parliament Act (1911), the Representation of People Acts (1918 and 1969), the Human Rights Act (1998), etc. (Leyland, 2012, 9. 39-40). The next source is common law, which means that the decisions that judges make in a legal case have an effect on future legal cases in this country. Certain legal cases have expanded the power of common law; for instance, Entick v Carrington put limits on the power of the Secretary of the State and the Crown to interfere with a person or property. However, legal decisions can be overruled by later statutes. After 1973, when the UK joined the European Union, its laws have also become part of the UK constitution.

The laws include the European Communities Act (1972), the Treaty of Rome (1957) and the subsequent treaties and the treaty of Lisbon (2007). The treaties were incorporated into the legal system of the UK by corresponding statutes (Leyland, 2012, p. 40). The European Convention of Human Rights (1998) is also a part of the constitution. It gives a person a variety of rights and allows to sue the UK at the European Court of Human Rights in the case of offense (Huxley-Binns & Martin, 2014, p. 22-23). Because of the absence of a codified constitution, legal and academic treatises such as “The English Constitution” by Walter Bagehot become a source as well (Leyland, 2012, p. 41-42).

As it can be seen, the principles of government, the rights and freedoms of individuals, the relations between governmental institutions and the law-making principles are determined by the UK constitution, which coincides with the definition of a constitution. Even though it is not codified, the UK has a constitution.

However, the conclusion we arrived to is not shared by some thinkers and activists. An opinion exists that, to become a proper constitution, the existing constitution of the UK has to be codified, as it is a nearly common rule in the most countries of the world. Since the 1970-s, there have been multiple proposals to codify the constitution, both by groups and by individuals of various political background. It must be mentioned, though, that these proposals suggest altering the constitution along with its codifying. There is a tendency to demand popular sovereignty and to propose supplanting with constitutional supremacy, i.e. to allow judges overrule the acts of Parliament. The alteration within Parliament is often proposed; it mostly relates to the membership and the relationship with the executive branch. Various forms of the protection of rights are also suggested. Those, who propose the changes, plan to do it either through a series of amendments or through a referendum (Blick, 2011, p. 3-4).

As for my own judgment, I agree with Anthony King, who considers that the basic principles of the UK constitution are clear enough without writing them down, and explaining the details would produce a lengthy and complicated volume (King, 2011, p. 100-101). Apart from that, I do not support mixing the process of amendment with the process of codification, as those, who suggest codification projects, do. If there is a need to alter the constitution, it can be done without codification. I do not think there is a need to codify the constitution for any reasons other than following the example of foreign countries.

The problem of the UK constitution needs careful examination. The first step is to determine the meaning of the term “constitution.” Contrary to the popular belief, it means a set of principles of government rather than a document, in which these rules are written down. To make up a constitution, the rules should define the relationship between the parts of government and between people and government; they should describe the rights and freedoms enjoyed by people. Since the rules we have in the UK do fulfil these requirements, the UK has a valid constitution. The fact that it is not codified does not make it any less valid. The suggestions of codification have more to do with some changes in the rules than with the validity of the constitution.

Elliott, C., & Quinn, F. (2007). English legal system (8th ed.). Harlow, UK: Pearson Education Limited.

Huxley-Binns, R., & Martin, J. (2014). Unlocking the English legal system (Unlocking the law) (4th ed.). Hoboken, New Jersey: Taylor and Francis.

King, A. (2001). Does the United Kingdom still have a constitution? London, UK: Sweet & Maxwell.

King, A. (2011). Codifying – or not codifying – the UK constitution: A literature review . Web.

Leyland, P. (2012). The constitution of the United Kingdom: A contextual analysis (2nd ed.). Oxford: Hart Publishing.

Martin, E. (2003). Oxford dictionary of law (5th edition). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

  • Chicago (A-D)
  • Chicago (N-B)

IvyPanda. (2024, March 20). Uncodified Constitution of the United Kingdom. https://ivypanda.com/essays/uncodified-constitution-of-the-united-kingdom/

"Uncodified Constitution of the United Kingdom." IvyPanda , 20 Mar. 2024, ivypanda.com/essays/uncodified-constitution-of-the-united-kingdom/.

IvyPanda . (2024) 'Uncodified Constitution of the United Kingdom'. 20 March.

IvyPanda . 2024. "Uncodified Constitution of the United Kingdom." March 20, 2024. https://ivypanda.com/essays/uncodified-constitution-of-the-united-kingdom/.

1. IvyPanda . "Uncodified Constitution of the United Kingdom." March 20, 2024. https://ivypanda.com/essays/uncodified-constitution-of-the-united-kingdom/.

Bibliography

IvyPanda . "Uncodified Constitution of the United Kingdom." March 20, 2024. https://ivypanda.com/essays/uncodified-constitution-of-the-united-kingdom/.

  • Democracy in the Middle East
  • Theory of Structuration by Anthony Giddens
  • The Enterprise Resource Planning Codification
  • The Non-Codified Authorities and Homeland Security
  • Learning History Technique. Knowledge Capture and Codification
  • ‘What’s Your Strategy for Managing Knowledge?’ by Hansen, Nohria and Tierney
  • Rules of Evidence Analysis
  • Sharia System and Globalization
  • Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • US Government: Privacy and Presidential Power
  • Agriculture Improvement: The US Farm Bill
  • The Necessity to Change the Affirmative Action Laws
  • First Amendment in the US Modern Justice System
  • Ballot Initiative in the 13th Amendment
  • US Constitutional Amendments: Procedures Changes

BRIT POLITICS, Study, Learn,  Create, Inspire

About Constitutions

What are constitutions for?

How is the UK constitution different?

Does Britain need a codified constitution?

Does the UK constitution contain separation of powers and rule of law?

What are the sources of the British Constitution?

What is the most important source of the British Constitution?

Constitutional Reform

What constitutional changes have we seen in the UK?

Has the constitution become more democratic?

Has constitutional reform produced a stable constitutional settlement?

The Legal System

How are the civil courts system set out?

What is judicial precedent?

What is judicial review?

Why might a UK court decide an action is illegal?

Is the Judiciary independent?

Is the Judiciary too powerful?

Are citizens able to gain redress of grievances (problems)?

Are systems of redress for people good enough?

The Human Rights Act

How do human rights fit in the constitution?

What was in the Human Rights Act 1998?

Have UK  judges balanced human rights regardless of political opinion?

Exploring the Constitution

Exploring the Constitution banner

Does the UK need a codified constitution?

In the past this has been something discussed by experts but recent changes to the Constitution have broadened the debate on whether the UK needs a codified constitution.

How has the debate widened

Gordon Brown, when Prime Minister, raised the issue. The Yes campaign during the referendum for independence in Scotland made the need for a written constitution one of its arguments. In addition, further devolution has raised the constitutional position of English legislation and the Political and Constitutional Reform Select committee has carried out a consultation on whether we should have a codified constitution.

Arguments for a UK codified constitution

It would set limits to the power of Government.

In Britain, the Executive controls Parliament through the party system and legislation, which cannot be questioned by the courts, can be passed by a majority of one.

The Executive also has powers under the Royal Prerogative which do not need parliamentary approval.

Protecting human rights

The Human Rights Act can be repealed at any time by Parliament and so individual rights are not embedded as in other countries.

Governments have removed the right of suspected terrorists to a trial, increased the information that can be collected on individuals and are have tried to insert clauses in some Acts to try to limit judicial review.

A written constitution would allow the creation of a British set of human rights, if this was thought preferable to the current European ones.

Creating a process for change

There is no process of changing the Constitution.

Parties have often made changes because it suits them. Labour ended the Conservative majority in the House of Lords by removing the hereditary peers without having a plan for overall reform.

Fixed-Term Parliaments were introduced because it suited the Coalition parties despite problems it could cause in the future.

Constitutional change has sometimes been approved by referendum and sometimes not.

Changes that have been made have not been related to each other and left questions such as whether the House of Lords should reflect devolution.

The Constitution would be clear and interpreted by an independent judiciary.

Citizens would be aware of what the constitutional position was and have more certainty if they wanted to take issues to the courts.

There would be an educational value in people being able to see and read the Constitution.

Arguments against a UK codified constitution

There is no need to change..

More of the Constitution has been written down and areas have been established such as the independence of the Judiciary and a set of human rights.

Changes can be made to improve checks and balances, for example, by strengthening Parliament as against the Executive.

Reduces flexibility

The present Constitution is flexible and can easily be changed to reflect new political situations and broader social and economic change.

A codified constitution would be constantly subject to interpretation by judges which might prevent new policies – in the United States the new system of healthcare was only declared legal by the vote of one judge on the Supreme Court panel that considered the issue.

Too much involvement from the courts

Some areas should not be dealt with by the courts.  Ministerial Responsibility to Parliament is a key constitutional convention but it would not be appropriate for the courts to rule on whether a Minster’s answer to a Parliamentary question was adequate enough to meet a constitutional provision. The Constitution has been able to adapt to the changes needed to cope with a Coalition Government.

How would it actually happen?

If the constitution was codified there are two options, one is to write down what the current constitutional rules are now and another is to produce a reformed constitution that deals with current uncertainties.

Either method is difficult, particularly as there are profound divisions among politicians over the European Union, reform of the House of Lords, the English Question, the Human Rights Act and the electoral system.

Even if the constitution included parliamentary sovereignty as a principle, once there is a codified constitution, judges would be bound to assess Acts of Parliament against the Constitution.

It would shift power away from democracy

A codified constitution would shift power from the democratically elected House of Commons to the unelected Judiciary.

Constitutional crises are best sorted by politicians and democratic pressure can create the demand for changes as with the Scottish referendum.

Statute Law Versus Common Law

Statute Law replaces common law as it is introduced and now covers the following key areas:-

–          The  Bill of Rights 1689  established Parliamentary Sovereignty which Dicey’s influential book of 1885 said was one of the two principles of the British Constitution

–          The  Representation of the People Acts  and, more recently, the  Parties, Elections and Referendums Act, 2000  and the  Fixed-term Parliaments Act 2011  set out who can vote and the rules for elections and parties

–          The  European Communities Act 1972  establishes Britain’s relationship with EU institutions and makes EU law superior to British law.

–          The  Human Rights Act 1998  creates a clear set of rights in British Law for the first time

–          The Devolution legislation defines the areas of responsibility for the devolved assemblies as against Westminster and has made Britain a partly federal state

These Acts set out a large number of the areas that a written constitution would contain.

They can, however, be changed by a future Parliament with just a majority of MPs present voting for the change so they are not embedded in the way that other constitutions, which require special procedures, are.

It is becoming accepted that constitutional changes require approval by the electorate but not all proposals have been subject to a referendum.

The Common Law has declined in significance but still contains important aspects of the constitution:-

–          The rule of law which was Dicey’s second essential principle of the British Constitution underpins common law as it has been developed by the Judiciary. No one is above the law and all have access to justice through the legal system.

–          The judges have created a process of judicial review of decisions by public bodies with a set of rules as to how cases should be decided.

–          The royal prerogative is the part of common law which defines the powers of the Executive, which it can exercise without Parliamentary approval, and include areas such as the declaration of war.

These areas of common law have been created by judges through deciding cases before them and are different from judicial interpretation of Acts of Parliament by which the judges use statute law to decide cases.

Increasing judicial independence may mean that judges use principle of the rule of law to challenge Legislation and Government attempts to change the Constitution more often.

Constitutional conventions

Constitutional conventions are rules that are accepted by the key figures in the political system.  They mainly regulate the role of the monarch, the appointment of the Prime Minister and the role of the Cabinet and Ministers.  The Salisbury Convention defines when the Lords can reject or delay legislation that the Commons wants and the Seward Convention requires the Scottish Parliament to be consulted on Westminster legislation affecting devolved areas.  It could be debated as to whether conventions are part of the constitution as they do not have the force of law and can be ignored if political circumstances make them inconvenient.

Authoritative works may occasionally be consulted by judges to help them to interpret the law in relation to the constitution.

should the uk codify its constitution essay

Previous Next

Privacy Overview

Marked by Teachers

  • TOP CATEGORIES
  • AS and A Level
  • University Degree
  • International Baccalaureate
  • Uncategorised
  • 5 Star Essays
  • Study Tools
  • Study Guides
  • Meet the Team
  • United Kingdom

Should the UK have a codified constitution?

Authors Avatar

A constitution is a set of rules that establishes how political power should be distributed, the relationship between political institutions, the limits to government, the rights of citizens and how the constitution can be changed. In the UK, we have an un-codified constitution; this means that it is not written down on one single document. However, recently more and more people have become in favour of codifying the constitution. There are many arguments justifying the employment of a codified constitution in the UK, but the most important are to limit the executive and legislative powers, entrench the constitution to protect the people and to modernize the UK politically compared to all other modern democracies that have a codified constitution.

In the 21 st  century, most democracies have a codified constitution with the exception of the UK, New Zealand, Israel and Saudi Arabia. This brings in to question how relevant and up to date the UK’s political system is. Currently, the constitution has evolved through conventions and changes to the law by parliament. Supporters of an un-codified constitution argue that the system works well using the current system which has been used for centuries, causing no problems. Another argument is the difficulties of codifying the British constitution, some of the problems that may incur may involve who, how and what should be in the constitution. The benefits of codification are just not worth the time and cost.

Join now!

This is a preview of the whole essay

However an important benefit of codifying the constitution is the existence of entrenchment, which would protect it from any changes unless it has support and in the long-term interest of the country. This would protect British citizens from dictatorship, which many could argue, is in place now. Parliamentary sovereignty defines the politics of the UK; any laws passed are in effect, changes to the constitution. Until the creation of the coalition in May 2010, most governments were the majority party in parliament, this created a system of elective dictatorship where most bills the government put forward in the House of Commons were passed. This questions how democratic and representative parliament currently is. Many people argue that there is too much power centralised at parliament and Westminster, codifying the constitution would clearly limit Westminster’s power and effectively stop Parliamentary sovereignty. However, by limiting the power of Westminster, it would be difficult for parliament to make changes to the law and bypass the red tape of the constitution. In cases of national emergency, where quick decision need to be made parliament would find it difficult to make a decision which does not change the constitution. For example, after the 7/7 bombings in London, parliament was able to pass the Terrorism Act 2006 which allowed suspects to be detained for up to 28 days without charge. In the United States, where the constitution is of such high authority that changes are very difficult, congress takes a long time to approve bills unless it is supported by both the Democrats and Republicans.  

In the USA, where the constitution is codified, the document is almost worshipped to the point where Americans can quote directly from it. It creates a sense of patriotism among Americans to refer to this document which their forefathers wrote by hand on the founding of the United States. It also makes the American people more politically aware of politics and their individual rights. If the UK were to codify the constitution, not only would this occur, but having the constitution on one single document would be educational for future citizens and children. However, over time the constitution may become out of date like in America, where the right to bear arms is increasingly becoming a topic for debate. Because the “right to bear arms” is in the constitution, conservatives like the Republicans are reluctant to change it.

The most important argument for the UK to have a codified constitution is that it would protect the individual rights of citizens. Although recently parliament has passed the Human Rights Act 1998 which came into force on 2 nd  October 2000, parliament can theoretically out rule this Act and pass another law to abolish the Human Rights Act. Parliament can take away our rights at anytime, brining into question whether they should have so much power. A codified constitution would prevent parliament from doing this and safeguard the rights of the people because it is a ‘higher’ law as opposed to a ‘common’ law. On the other hand, a codified constitution would bring the judiciary into politics. The exact meaning of constitutions and how they can be interpreted is often disputed, in the USA this is settled in the Supreme Court resulting in unelected judges having presiding power of the constitution. Critics argue that judges should not have this power, because they have not been elected by the people. What makes them different to a normal citizen politically? Also, the UK Supreme Court is relatively new, and it may not have the reliability compared to other powers such as parliament.

The UK should therefore not codify it’s constitution due to the many reasons against it, until such a time when codification is needed, the current system should continue to be implemented until there is a wide call for change or the codification of the constitution by the majority of the people e.g. if in a referendum more than 50% vote Yes for the codification of the UK constitution.

Should the UK have a codified constitution?

Document Details

  • Word Count 910
  • Page Count 2
  • Level AS and A Level
  • Subject Politics

Related Essays

Should the UK have a codified constitution?

Essay plan - The UK should not have a codified constitution

Should the UK constitution remain un-codified?

Should the UK constitution remain un-codified?

Make out a case against the adoption of a codified constitution for the UK

Make out a case against the adoption of a codified constitution for the UK

IMAGES

  1. What is the UK Constitution?

    should the uk codify its constitution essay

  2. Should Britain have a codified constitution?

    should the uk codify its constitution essay

  3. Designing a Constitutional Convention

    should the uk codify its constitution essay

  4. Principles of the UK Constitution Essay Plan

    should the uk codify its constitution essay

  5. UK Constitution

    should the uk codify its constitution essay

  6. UK Constitution Detailed Notes + ESSAY PLAN| BUNDLE

    should the uk codify its constitution essay

VIDEO

  1. 20 Lines about Constitution of India

  2. Employment Law and HR Update

  3. The UK Constitution

  4. Norman Woods joins the Lars Larson Show

  5. 10 lines on Indian Constitution in English

  6. Connecticut: Fundamental Orders and Constitutional System

COMMENTS

  1. Public law Essay- Should The UK Codify It's Constitution?

    Another minor but credible argument is that there is no need for a written constitution in the UK. According to the majority, the unwritten constitution has played a very important role in the success of a democracy in the UK so there is no real or urgent need for a written constitution as of right now. WHY THE UK SHOULD AVOID A WRITTEN ...

  2. Arguments For and Against the UK Having a Written Constitution

    'Why The UK Needs A Written Constitution' (politics.co.uk, 2018) accessed 19 January 2018. [4] 'The Nuremberg Laws' ( National Archives , 2018) accessed 19 January 2018. [5] AnthonyHolland Lseacuk, 'Those Who Say "The Status Quo Is Not An Option" Need Evidence That the Alternative Would Be Better' (Constitution UK, 30 September ...

  3. Should the UK Constitution be codified?

    the Select Committee may find useful in its current work. B - Outline 5. As will emerge from what follows, in the argument about whether the UK constitution is legal or political in nature, I am very firmly on the side of those who think it is political, rather than legal. I am also very firmly of the view that that is how things should be. 6.

  4. PDF Constitutional Conventions in the United Kingdom: Should they be codified?

    This essay seeks to examine whether constitutional conventions should be codified if the United Kingdom were to adopt a codified constitution. There is the choice to codify and legally enforce them, codify them and leave them as non-legal guidelines, codify a selection or finally, not codify them at all; each

  5. Britain's constitution after Brexit

    Josh Simons gives his perspective on the case to codify the constitution of the UK and why the UK must now reach an enduring constitutional settlement. Brexit stimulated broad engagement with the politics of Britain's constitution. For three years, citizens who felt they had made a constitutional decision, and those who sought to reverse it ...

  6. Codifying the UK Constitutional Arrangements

    This essay will attempt to analyse theoretical and practical arguments for and against codifying the UK's constitutional arrangements. A constitution is a set of rules which regulates the balance of powers in a country between the Judiciary, Executive, Legislature and a citizen. Constitutions differ enormously in their volume and scope.

  7. Should Britain Adopt a Written Constitution?

    Additionally, the existence of only a few other countries in the world that do not have a codified constitution, along with recent constitutional reforms such as the Human Rights Act of 1998 and the Constitutional Reform Act of 2005, have rekindled the debate on whether or not the UK should codify its constitution (McHarg, 2008). This essay ...

  8. Why Britain needs a written constitution

    The UK does not lack constitutional documents; one of its problems is that it possesses too many. There is another reason why the imperatives of modern warfare progressively obliged states to ...

  9. The challenge for those who wish to codify the UK's constitution is to

    Written constitutions tend to be codified when power relations are substantially changed in a political system. Frank Vibert considers whether the UK is experiencing such a moment and debates the practical and philosophical benefits and drawbacks to putting the constitutional pen to paper.. On December 8 th the House of Commons Committee on Political and Constitutional Reform held a hearing on ...

  10. PDF The British Constitution after Brexit (8)

    The British Constitution after Brexit - The case for popular codification 2 I. Introduction On the face of it, British politics is back to normal. After three years of constitutional wrangling, a stable government has delivered on its mandate to transform the UK constitution by leaving the European Union (EU).

  11. PDF To Codify or Not to Codify?

    the UK's constitution throughout this report. However, it is important to remember that this is only our subjective interpretation of the UK constitution; there is no formally recognised constitutional document in the UK. The third section compares the content of the UK's constitution to other constitutions in force around the world. In ...

  12. What is the UK Constitution?

    This is the reason why the UK has not felt the need to codify its constitution. But the UK does have a constitution, to be found in leading statutes, conventions, judicial decisions, and treaties. Examples of constitutional statutes include the Bill of Rights 1689, Acts of Union 1707 and 1800, Act of Settlement 1701, Parliament Acts 1911 and ...

  13. A Written Constitution: A Case Not Made

    Abstract. Whether the UK needs a written constitution is a staple of British constitutional debates. Over the years, the fault lines have shifted from whether to incorporate a Bill of Rights to much deeper disagreement with respect to the people and the central power of the state. In this article I neither endorse the conservative case against ...

  14. Should the UK Adopt a Codified Constitution?

    Should the UK Adopt a Codified Constitution? Arguments in favour include: It would provide clear rules, with less confusion as to what the constitution means. It would formally limit the powers of government, addressing the problem of elective dictatorship. It could be policed and protected by judges, who are politically independent and neutral.

  15. To codify or not to codify the UK constitution? Advantages and

    This essay aims at reflecting on the persistent relevance of the traditional distinction between 'written' and 'unwritten' law as an essential feature of the English legal tradition, in order to better understand the current discussion concerning the enactment of a written Constitution for the United Kingdom, after the wide public ...

  16. To Codify or Not To Codify? Lessons from ...

    In doing so, we are able to identify, with great precision, the topics addressed in other countries' constitutions but omitted from constitutionally relevant statutes in the UK. Reflecting on the topics 'missing' from the UK's constitution offers three lessons for those contemplating further codification of the UK's constitution: 1.

  17. Mapping the path to codifying

    Mapping the path to codifying - or not codifying - the UK's constitution. Written evidence submitted by Unlock Democracy (CDE 07) 1. Unlock Democracy is the UK's leading campaign for democracy, rights and freedoms. A grassroots movement, we are owned and run by our members. In particular, we campaign for fair, open and honest elections ...

  18. Does the UK need a codified constitution?

    An evaluation of the latest developments in the debate over whether the UK should codify its constitution. All major exam boards require a full understanding of constitutional changes since 1997. In addition, the AQA specification references 'issues and debates around recent constitutional changes' and Edexcel asks whether the UK should ...

  19. Uncodified Constitution of the United Kingdom Essay

    The European Convention of Human Rights (1998) is also a part of the constitution. It gives a person a variety of rights and allows to sue the UK at the European Court of Human Rights in the case of offense (Huxley-Binns & Martin, 2014, p. 22-23). Because of the absence of a codified constitution, legal and academic treatises such as "The ...

  20. Does the UK need a codified constitution?

    The Constitution would be clear and interpreted by an independent judiciary. Citizens would be aware of what the constitutional position was and have more certainty if they wanted to take issues to the courts. There would be an educational value in people being able to see and read the Constitution. Arguments against a UK codified constitution

  21. Should the UK codify its Constitution or not?

    Should the UK's constitution remain uncodified? Use relevant examples to support your points. The word "constitution" is defined by Oxford as ' a body of fundamental principles or established precedents according to which a state or other organization is acknowledged to be governed'.In essence it sets out the framework and principals that government within the state have to adhere too.

  22. Should the UK have a codified constitution?

    A constitution is a set of rules that establishes how political power should be distributed, the relationship between political institutions, the limits to government, the rights of citizens and how the constitution can be changed. In the UK, we have an un-codified constitution; this means that it is not written down on one single document.