Book cover

Philosophy in Educational Research pp 213–232 Cite as

Educational Theory, Practice, and Research: Pragmatic Perspectives

  • David Bridges 2 , 3 , 4  
  • First Online: 02 December 2016

2861 Accesses

I conceded in Chap.  5 that academic, discipline-based research, whatever its importance and interest, had problems in engaging directly with practice, especially when this practice is understood in terms of the agency of an individual practitioner working with a socially derived, but uniquely personal, set of constructs in a highly particular working context. I pointed to a developing tradition of practitioner research, and, more particularly, action research, as a response to this analysis of the kind of research which was needed for engagement with practice. In such research, teachers might test ideas, hypotheses, and theory—including their own tacitly or self-consciously held theory—against experience in their own classroom and modify practice in the light of such testing. Such an approach to the development of understanding and practice is, of course, not without its own philosophical underpinnings. In this case these lie pretty firmly in the tradition of philosophical pragmatism, which I introduced in Chap.  12 on theories of truth. Pragmatism is a particularly attractive position (or set of positions) in the context of what might be considered as applied research such as education, since its claims to truth, validity, or at least utility are tested precisely through its application and an examination of the consequences of that action. I suggest, then, that this is an area that merits closer attention and that a better understanding of the character, strengths, and weaknesses of philosophical pragmatism may help us to understand too the strengths and weaknesses of its application in educational research including, more specifically, practitioner and action research.

The original version of this chapter was published in Bridges, D. (2003) Fiction written under oath: Essays in philosophy and educational research , Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution .

Buying options

  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
  • Durable hardcover edition

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Papastephanou does however go on to refer to other philosophical traditions that have contributed ‘in varying degrees and selectively’ to different formulations of action research, including MacIntyre and Aristotelian thought, Habermas and, in the case of Kemmis and Carr ‘ Ideologiekritik of a Marxist origin’ (Papastephanou 2007 : 171).

For Dewey, of course, it was critical that this interest or ‘reflective attention’ is an authentic one for the learner, rather than one imposed as the result of coercion or bribery. Dewey writes of ‘the fundamental necessity (of) leading the child to realise a problem of his own, so that he is self-induced to attend in order to find out its answer’ (Dewey 1990 : 149). He explains, ‘True, reflective attention … always involves judging, reasoning, deliberation; it means that the child has a question of his own , and is actively engaged in seeking and selecting relevant material with which to answer it, considering the bearings and relations of this material—the kind of solution it calls for. The problem is one’s own; hence also the training secured is one’s own—it is discipline, or gain in power of control; that is a habit of considering problems …’ (Dewey 1990 : 148, his italics).

Garrison observes that ‘many in the field of education have not recognized that Dewey held a constructivist view of knowledge’ (Garrison 1994 : 5), and indeed McCarthy and Sears ( 2000 ) emphatically challenge Garrison’s view on this.

McCarthy and Sears ( 2000 ) argue, however, that ‘The Deweyan-pragmatic perspective … is one that is ontologically realist and requires, epistemologically, a correspondence theory of truth, of a particular kind that Dewey very carefully explicates’ (McCarthy and Sears 2000 : 213).

Coming out of the UK educational research community, I resort fairly naturally to the language of ‘action research’ where some, for example, North American colleagues might use the language of ‘practitioner research’. Anderson et al. ( 1994 ) suggest indeed that ‘practitioner research and action research, the preferred term in Britain, are sometimes used interchangeably,’ (1994: 20). They share the characteristics of: (i) engaging practitioners as researchers (usually in their own domain of practice); and (ii) a particular focus on the situated and often tacit knowledge of practitioners. Action research suggests, however, a cyclical process of the testing of ideas in practice, and with it the kind of pragmatic philosophy indicated here, which is not a necessarily feature of all forms of practitioner research. For a discussion of these issues by reference to the US, see also Cochran-Smith and Lytle ( 1993 ).

Adelman judges this to be the most difficult phase of action research: ‘To move from felt “troubles” and “anxieties” to a statement of an issue, teachers have to engage in persistent reflexive thought about their own and others’ practices’ (Adelman 1993 : 18).

There is, of course, the reciprocal implication that the conceptual apparatus which informs our understanding of education needs to be constantly challenged, modified, and informed by experience and ideas arising from that experience.

‘The risk … is that a policy-maker’s view of really useful research will resemble Margaret Thatcher’s view of a really useful Minister … that it takes the problems which government brings to it, contributes to their solution, and refrains from adding new problems or further complicating old ones’ (Edwards 2000 : 304).

Adelman, C. (1993). Kurt Lewin and the origins of action research. Educational Action Research, 1 (1), 7–24.

Article   Google Scholar  

Anderson, G. L., Herr, K., & Nihlen, A. (1994). Studying your own school: An educator’s guide to qualitative practitioner research . Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

Google Scholar  

Argyris, C., Putnam, R., & MacLain Smith, D. (1985). Action science . San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.

Bagehot, W. (1905). Shakespeare—The individual. In Literary studies by the late Walter Bagehot . London: Longman Green.

Ben-Peretz, M., & Rumney, S. (1991). Professional thinking in guided practice. Teaching and Teacher Education, 7 (5/6), 517–530.

Berliner, D. C. (1987). Ways of thinking about students and classrooms by more and less experienced teachers. In J. Calderhead (Ed.), Exploring teacher’s thinking . London: Cassell.

Bernstein, R. J. (1967). John Dewey. In P. Edwards (Ed.), The encyclopaedia of philosophy (Vol. 1, pp. 380–385). New York: MacMillan/The Free Press.

Bridges, D. (1994). Transferable skills in higher education: A philosophical perspective. In D. Bridges (Ed.), Transferable skills in higher education . Norwich: University of East Anglia/ERTEC.

Bridges, D., Smeyers, P., & Smith, R. D. (2009). Evidence-based education policy: What evidence? What basis? Whose policy? . Chichester: Wiley Blackwell.

Burkhardt, F. H. (Ed.). (1977). A Pluralistic universe: The works of William James . Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

Calderhead, J. (1987). The quality of reflection in student teachers’ professional learning. European Journal of Teacher Education, 10 (3), 269–278.

Calderhead, J. (1988). Learning from introductory schools experience. Journal of Education for Teaching, 14 (1), 75–83.

Cherryholmes, C. H. (1992). Notes on pragmatism and scientific realism. Educational Researcher, 21 (6), 13–17.

Cherryholmes, C. H. (1994). More notes on pragmatism. Educational Researcher, 23 (1), 16–18.

Chinn, C. A., & Brewer, W. K. (1993). The role of anomalous data in knowledge. Review of educational acquisition: A theoretical framework and implications for science instruction. Review of Educational Research, 63 (1), 1–49.

Clarke, C. (1994). Some reflections on reflecting practitioners. In Papers of the Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain , Mimeo.

Cochran-Smith, M., & Lytle, S. (1993). Inside-outside: Teacher research and knowledge . New York: Teachers’ College Press.

Copeland, W. D. (1981). Clinical experiences in the education of teachers. Journal of Education for Teaching, 7 (1), 3–16.

Dewey, J. (1916). Democracy and education . New York: Macmillan.

Dewey, J. (1981). Experience and nature. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), John Dewey: The later works 1925 – 53 , Vol. 1. Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL: Southern Illinois University Press (Originally published 1925).

Dewey, J. (1984). Philosophy and civilisation. In J. A. Boydston (Ed.), John Dewey: The later works 1925 – 53 , Vol. 3. Carbondale and Edwardsville, IL: Southern Illinois University Press (Originally published 1927).

Dewey, J. (1990). The development of attention. In J. Dewey (Ed.), The school and society: The child and the curriculum . Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Dewey, J. (1998a). The development of American pragmatism. In L. A. Hickman & T. M. Alexander (Eds.), The essential Dewey: Volume 1: Pragmatism, education, democracy . Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press (Originally published 1925).

Dewey, J. (1998b). Reconstructing philosophy. In L. A. Hickman & T. M. Alexander (Eds.), The essential Dewey: Volume 1: Pragmatism, education, democracy . Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press (Originally published 1928).

Easen, P. (1992). Practice development in the primary school: Collaboration and conflict . Ph.D. Thesis, University of Newcastle-upon-Tyne.

Edwards, T. (2000). ‘All the evidence shows …’: Reasonable expectations of educationalresearch. Oxford Review of Education, 26 (3/4), 299–312.

Eisner, E. (1993). Forms of understanding and the future of research. Educational Researcher, 22 (7), 5–11.

Elbaz, F. (1988). Critical reflection on teaching: Insights from Freire. Journal of Education for Teaching, 14 (2), 171–187.

Fisch, M. H. (1954). Alexander Bain and the genealogy of pragmatism. Journal of the History of Ideas, 15 (3), 413–444.

Freire, P. (1972). Pedagogy of the oppressed . Harmondsworth: Penguin.

Garrison, J. (1994). Realism, Deweyan pragmatism and educational research. Educational Researcher, 23 (1), 5–14.

Garrison, J. (1995). Deweyan pragmatism and the epistemology of social constructivism. American Educational Research Journal, 32 (4), 716–740.

Garrison, J. (1996). The unity of the activity: A response to Prawat. Educational Researcher, 25 (6), 21–23.

Glassman, M. (2001). Dewey and Vygotsky: Society, experience and inquiry in educational practice. Educational Researcher, 30 (4), 3–14.

Handal, G. (1991). Collective time—Collective practice. The Curriculum Journal, 2 (3), 317–334.

House, E. R. (1991). Realism in research. Educational Researcher, 20 (6), 2–9.

House, E. R. (1992). Response to ‘Notes on pragmatism and scientific realism’. Educational Researcher, 21 (6), 18–19.

House, E. R. (1994). Is John Dewey eternal? Educational Researcher, 23 (1), 15–16.

Kant, I. (1958 edn). Groundwork of the metaphysic of morals (H. J. Paton, Trans.) New York: Harper and Row.

Kennedy, M. K. (1997). The connection between research and practice. Educational Researcher, 26 (7), 4–12.

Kolb, D. A. (1984). Experiential learning: Experience as a source of learning and development . New Jersey: Prentice Hall.

Lewis, C. I. (1929). Mind and the world order: An outline of a theory of knowledge . New York: Scribners Sons.

McCarthy, C. L., & Sears, E. (2000). Deweyan pragmatism and the quest for true belief. Educational Theory, 50 (2), 213–227.

MacKinnon, A. M. (1987). Toward a conceptualisation of a reflective practice in science teaching . Paper presented at the Second International Seminar: Misconceptions in Science and Mathematics, Cornell University, Department of Math and Science Education, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC.

Maynard, T., & Furlong, J. (1993). Learning to teach and models of mentoring . Paper presented to Bedford/ERTEC conference on mentoring (mimeo).

Munby, H., & Russell, T. (1989). Educating the reflective teacher: An essay review of two books by Donald Schön. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 21 (1), 71–80.

Murphey, M. G. (1961). The development of Peirce’s philosophy . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Ohanian, S. (1994). Who’s in charge? A teacher speaks her mind . Portsmouth, NH: Heineman.

Papastephanou, M. (2007). Philosophical research and educational action research. In D. Bridges & R. D. Smith (Eds.), Philosophy, methodology and educational research . Oxford: Blackwell.

Polanyi, M. (1966). The tacit dimension . Garden City, NJ: Doubleday.

Prawat, R. S. (1993). The value of ideas: Problems versus possibilities in learning. Educational Researcher, 22 (2), 5–16.

Prawat, R. S. (1995). Misreading Dewey: Reform, projects and the language game. Educational Researcher, 24 (7), 13–22.

Prawat, R. S., & Floden, R. E. (1994). Philosophical perspectives on constructivist views of learning. Educational Psychologist, 29 (1), 37–48.

Roszak, T. (1967). On academic delinquency. In T. Roszak (Ed.), The dissenting academy: Essays criticizing the teaching of the humanities in American Universities . Harmondsworth: Penguin.

Scheffler, I. (1974). Four pragmatists . London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Schön, D. A. (1983). The reflective practitioner: How professionals think in action . New York: Basic Books.

Smeyers, P., & Depaepe, M. (2006). Educational research: Why ‘what works’ does not work . Dordrecht: Springer.

Stenhouse, L. (1980). What counts as research? Unpublished mimeo. Norwich: CARE Archive, University of East Anglia.

Thayer, H. S. (1967). Pragmatism. In P. Edwards (Ed.), The encyclopaedia of philosophy (Vol. 5, pp. 430–436). New York: MacMillan/The Free Press.

Download references

Author information

Authors and affiliations.

Professor Emeritus, University of East Anglia, Norwich, UK

David Bridges

Emeritus Fellow, St. Edmund’s College, Cambridge, UK

Emeritus Fellow, Homerton College, Cambridge, UK

You can also search for this author in PubMed   Google Scholar

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Bridges .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter.

Bridges, D. (2017). Educational Theory, Practice, and Research: Pragmatic Perspectives. In: Philosophy in Educational Research. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-49212-4_13

Download citation

DOI : https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-49212-4_13

Published : 02 December 2016

Publisher Name : Springer, Cham

Print ISBN : 978-3-319-49210-0

Online ISBN : 978-3-319-49212-4

eBook Packages : Education Education (R0)

Share this chapter

Anyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:

Sorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.

Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative

  • Publish with us

Policies and ethics

  • Find a journal
  • Track your research
  • Search Menu
  • Browse content in Arts and Humanities
  • Browse content in Archaeology
  • Anglo-Saxon and Medieval Archaeology
  • Archaeological Methodology and Techniques
  • Archaeology by Region
  • Archaeology of Religion
  • Archaeology of Trade and Exchange
  • Biblical Archaeology
  • Contemporary and Public Archaeology
  • Environmental Archaeology
  • Historical Archaeology
  • History and Theory of Archaeology
  • Industrial Archaeology
  • Landscape Archaeology
  • Mortuary Archaeology
  • Prehistoric Archaeology
  • Underwater Archaeology
  • Urban Archaeology
  • Zooarchaeology
  • Browse content in Architecture
  • Architectural Structure and Design
  • History of Architecture
  • Residential and Domestic Buildings
  • Theory of Architecture
  • Browse content in Art
  • Art Subjects and Themes
  • History of Art
  • Industrial and Commercial Art
  • Theory of Art
  • Biographical Studies
  • Byzantine Studies
  • Browse content in Classical Studies
  • Classical History
  • Classical Philosophy
  • Classical Mythology
  • Classical Literature
  • Classical Reception
  • Classical Art and Architecture
  • Classical Oratory and Rhetoric
  • Greek and Roman Epigraphy
  • Greek and Roman Law
  • Greek and Roman Archaeology
  • Greek and Roman Papyrology
  • Late Antiquity
  • Religion in the Ancient World
  • Digital Humanities
  • Browse content in History
  • Colonialism and Imperialism
  • Diplomatic History
  • Environmental History
  • Genealogy, Heraldry, Names, and Honours
  • Genocide and Ethnic Cleansing
  • Historical Geography
  • History by Period
  • History of Agriculture
  • History of Education
  • History of Emotions
  • History of Gender and Sexuality
  • Industrial History
  • Intellectual History
  • International History
  • Labour History
  • Legal and Constitutional History
  • Local and Family History
  • Maritime History
  • Military History
  • National Liberation and Post-Colonialism
  • Oral History
  • Political History
  • Public History
  • Regional and National History
  • Revolutions and Rebellions
  • Slavery and Abolition of Slavery
  • Social and Cultural History
  • Theory, Methods, and Historiography
  • Urban History
  • World History
  • Browse content in Language Teaching and Learning
  • Language Learning (Specific Skills)
  • Language Teaching Theory and Methods
  • Browse content in Linguistics
  • Applied Linguistics
  • Cognitive Linguistics
  • Computational Linguistics
  • Forensic Linguistics
  • Grammar, Syntax and Morphology
  • Historical and Diachronic Linguistics
  • History of English
  • Language Acquisition
  • Language Variation
  • Language Families
  • Language Evolution
  • Language Reference
  • Lexicography
  • Linguistic Theories
  • Linguistic Typology
  • Linguistic Anthropology
  • Phonetics and Phonology
  • Psycholinguistics
  • Sociolinguistics
  • Translation and Interpretation
  • Writing Systems
  • Browse content in Literature
  • Bibliography
  • Children's Literature Studies
  • Literary Studies (Asian)
  • Literary Studies (European)
  • Literary Studies (Eco-criticism)
  • Literary Studies (Modernism)
  • Literary Studies (Romanticism)
  • Literary Studies (American)
  • Literary Studies - World
  • Literary Studies (1500 to 1800)
  • Literary Studies (19th Century)
  • Literary Studies (20th Century onwards)
  • Literary Studies (African American Literature)
  • Literary Studies (British and Irish)
  • Literary Studies (Early and Medieval)
  • Literary Studies (Fiction, Novelists, and Prose Writers)
  • Literary Studies (Gender Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Graphic Novels)
  • Literary Studies (History of the Book)
  • Literary Studies (Plays and Playwrights)
  • Literary Studies (Poetry and Poets)
  • Literary Studies (Postcolonial Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Queer Studies)
  • Literary Studies (Science Fiction)
  • Literary Studies (Travel Literature)
  • Literary Studies (War Literature)
  • Literary Studies (Women's Writing)
  • Literary Theory and Cultural Studies
  • Mythology and Folklore
  • Shakespeare Studies and Criticism
  • Browse content in Media Studies
  • Browse content in Music
  • Applied Music
  • Dance and Music
  • Ethics in Music
  • Ethnomusicology
  • Gender and Sexuality in Music
  • Medicine and Music
  • Music Cultures
  • Music and Religion
  • Music and Culture
  • Music and Media
  • Music Education and Pedagogy
  • Music Theory and Analysis
  • Musical Scores, Lyrics, and Libretti
  • Musical Structures, Styles, and Techniques
  • Musicology and Music History
  • Performance Practice and Studies
  • Race and Ethnicity in Music
  • Sound Studies
  • Browse content in Performing Arts
  • Browse content in Philosophy
  • Aesthetics and Philosophy of Art
  • Epistemology
  • Feminist Philosophy
  • History of Western Philosophy
  • Metaphysics
  • Moral Philosophy
  • Non-Western Philosophy
  • Philosophy of Science
  • Philosophy of Action
  • Philosophy of Law
  • Philosophy of Religion
  • Philosophy of Language
  • Philosophy of Mind
  • Philosophy of Perception
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
  • Practical Ethics
  • Social and Political Philosophy
  • Browse content in Religion
  • Biblical Studies
  • Christianity
  • East Asian Religions
  • History of Religion
  • Judaism and Jewish Studies
  • Qumran Studies
  • Religion and Education
  • Religion and Health
  • Religion and Politics
  • Religion and Science
  • Religion and Law
  • Religion and Art, Literature, and Music
  • Religious Studies
  • Browse content in Society and Culture
  • Cookery, Food, and Drink
  • Cultural Studies
  • Customs and Traditions
  • Ethical Issues and Debates
  • Hobbies, Games, Arts and Crafts
  • Lifestyle, Home, and Garden
  • Natural world, Country Life, and Pets
  • Popular Beliefs and Controversial Knowledge
  • Sports and Outdoor Recreation
  • Technology and Society
  • Travel and Holiday
  • Visual Culture
  • Browse content in Law
  • Arbitration
  • Browse content in Company and Commercial Law
  • Commercial Law
  • Company Law
  • Browse content in Comparative Law
  • Systems of Law
  • Competition Law
  • Browse content in Constitutional and Administrative Law
  • Government Powers
  • Judicial Review
  • Local Government Law
  • Military and Defence Law
  • Parliamentary and Legislative Practice
  • Construction Law
  • Contract Law
  • Browse content in Criminal Law
  • Criminal Procedure
  • Criminal Evidence Law
  • Sentencing and Punishment
  • Employment and Labour Law
  • Environment and Energy Law
  • Browse content in Financial Law
  • Banking Law
  • Insolvency Law
  • History of Law
  • Human Rights and Immigration
  • Intellectual Property Law
  • Browse content in International Law
  • Private International Law and Conflict of Laws
  • Public International Law
  • IT and Communications Law
  • Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law
  • Law and Politics
  • Law and Society
  • Browse content in Legal System and Practice
  • Courts and Procedure
  • Legal Skills and Practice
  • Primary Sources of Law
  • Regulation of Legal Profession
  • Medical and Healthcare Law
  • Browse content in Policing
  • Criminal Investigation and Detection
  • Police and Security Services
  • Police Procedure and Law
  • Police Regional Planning
  • Browse content in Property Law
  • Personal Property Law
  • Study and Revision
  • Terrorism and National Security Law
  • Browse content in Trusts Law
  • Wills and Probate or Succession
  • Browse content in Medicine and Health
  • Browse content in Allied Health Professions
  • Arts Therapies
  • Clinical Science
  • Dietetics and Nutrition
  • Occupational Therapy
  • Operating Department Practice
  • Physiotherapy
  • Radiography
  • Speech and Language Therapy
  • Browse content in Anaesthetics
  • General Anaesthesia
  • Neuroanaesthesia
  • Browse content in Clinical Medicine
  • Acute Medicine
  • Cardiovascular Medicine
  • Clinical Genetics
  • Clinical Pharmacology and Therapeutics
  • Dermatology
  • Endocrinology and Diabetes
  • Gastroenterology
  • Genito-urinary Medicine
  • Geriatric Medicine
  • Infectious Diseases
  • Medical Oncology
  • Medical Toxicology
  • Pain Medicine
  • Palliative Medicine
  • Rehabilitation Medicine
  • Respiratory Medicine and Pulmonology
  • Rheumatology
  • Sleep Medicine
  • Sports and Exercise Medicine
  • Clinical Neuroscience
  • Community Medical Services
  • Critical Care
  • Emergency Medicine
  • Forensic Medicine
  • Haematology
  • History of Medicine
  • Browse content in Medical Dentistry
  • Oral and Maxillofacial Surgery
  • Paediatric Dentistry
  • Restorative Dentistry and Orthodontics
  • Surgical Dentistry
  • Medical Ethics
  • Browse content in Medical Skills
  • Clinical Skills
  • Communication Skills
  • Nursing Skills
  • Surgical Skills
  • Medical Statistics and Methodology
  • Browse content in Neurology
  • Clinical Neurophysiology
  • Neuropathology
  • Nursing Studies
  • Browse content in Obstetrics and Gynaecology
  • Gynaecology
  • Occupational Medicine
  • Ophthalmology
  • Otolaryngology (ENT)
  • Browse content in Paediatrics
  • Neonatology
  • Browse content in Pathology
  • Chemical Pathology
  • Clinical Cytogenetics and Molecular Genetics
  • Histopathology
  • Medical Microbiology and Virology
  • Patient Education and Information
  • Browse content in Pharmacology
  • Psychopharmacology
  • Browse content in Popular Health
  • Caring for Others
  • Complementary and Alternative Medicine
  • Self-help and Personal Development
  • Browse content in Preclinical Medicine
  • Cell Biology
  • Molecular Biology and Genetics
  • Reproduction, Growth and Development
  • Primary Care
  • Professional Development in Medicine
  • Browse content in Psychiatry
  • Addiction Medicine
  • Child and Adolescent Psychiatry
  • Forensic Psychiatry
  • Learning Disabilities
  • Old Age Psychiatry
  • Psychotherapy
  • Browse content in Public Health and Epidemiology
  • Epidemiology
  • Public Health
  • Browse content in Radiology
  • Clinical Radiology
  • Interventional Radiology
  • Nuclear Medicine
  • Radiation Oncology
  • Reproductive Medicine
  • Browse content in Surgery
  • Cardiothoracic Surgery
  • Gastro-intestinal and Colorectal Surgery
  • General Surgery
  • Neurosurgery
  • Paediatric Surgery
  • Peri-operative Care
  • Plastic and Reconstructive Surgery
  • Surgical Oncology
  • Transplant Surgery
  • Trauma and Orthopaedic Surgery
  • Vascular Surgery
  • Browse content in Science and Mathematics
  • Browse content in Biological Sciences
  • Aquatic Biology
  • Biochemistry
  • Bioinformatics and Computational Biology
  • Developmental Biology
  • Ecology and Conservation
  • Evolutionary Biology
  • Genetics and Genomics
  • Microbiology
  • Molecular and Cell Biology
  • Natural History
  • Plant Sciences and Forestry
  • Research Methods in Life Sciences
  • Structural Biology
  • Systems Biology
  • Zoology and Animal Sciences
  • Browse content in Chemistry
  • Analytical Chemistry
  • Computational Chemistry
  • Crystallography
  • Environmental Chemistry
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Inorganic Chemistry
  • Materials Chemistry
  • Medicinal Chemistry
  • Mineralogy and Gems
  • Organic Chemistry
  • Physical Chemistry
  • Polymer Chemistry
  • Study and Communication Skills in Chemistry
  • Theoretical Chemistry
  • Browse content in Computer Science
  • Artificial Intelligence
  • Computer Architecture and Logic Design
  • Game Studies
  • Human-Computer Interaction
  • Mathematical Theory of Computation
  • Programming Languages
  • Software Engineering
  • Systems Analysis and Design
  • Virtual Reality
  • Browse content in Computing
  • Business Applications
  • Computer Security
  • Computer Games
  • Computer Networking and Communications
  • Digital Lifestyle
  • Graphical and Digital Media Applications
  • Operating Systems
  • Browse content in Earth Sciences and Geography
  • Atmospheric Sciences
  • Environmental Geography
  • Geology and the Lithosphere
  • Maps and Map-making
  • Meteorology and Climatology
  • Oceanography and Hydrology
  • Palaeontology
  • Physical Geography and Topography
  • Regional Geography
  • Soil Science
  • Urban Geography
  • Browse content in Engineering and Technology
  • Agriculture and Farming
  • Biological Engineering
  • Civil Engineering, Surveying, and Building
  • Electronics and Communications Engineering
  • Energy Technology
  • Engineering (General)
  • Environmental Science, Engineering, and Technology
  • History of Engineering and Technology
  • Mechanical Engineering and Materials
  • Technology of Industrial Chemistry
  • Transport Technology and Trades
  • Browse content in Environmental Science
  • Applied Ecology (Environmental Science)
  • Conservation of the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Environmental Sustainability
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Environmental Science)
  • Management of Land and Natural Resources (Environmental Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environmental Science)
  • Nuclear Issues (Environmental Science)
  • Pollution and Threats to the Environment (Environmental Science)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Environmental Science)
  • History of Science and Technology
  • Browse content in Materials Science
  • Ceramics and Glasses
  • Composite Materials
  • Metals, Alloying, and Corrosion
  • Nanotechnology
  • Browse content in Mathematics
  • Applied Mathematics
  • Biomathematics and Statistics
  • History of Mathematics
  • Mathematical Education
  • Mathematical Finance
  • Mathematical Analysis
  • Numerical and Computational Mathematics
  • Probability and Statistics
  • Pure Mathematics
  • Browse content in Neuroscience
  • Cognition and Behavioural Neuroscience
  • Development of the Nervous System
  • Disorders of the Nervous System
  • History of Neuroscience
  • Invertebrate Neurobiology
  • Molecular and Cellular Systems
  • Neuroendocrinology and Autonomic Nervous System
  • Neuroscientific Techniques
  • Sensory and Motor Systems
  • Browse content in Physics
  • Astronomy and Astrophysics
  • Atomic, Molecular, and Optical Physics
  • Biological and Medical Physics
  • Classical Mechanics
  • Computational Physics
  • Condensed Matter Physics
  • Electromagnetism, Optics, and Acoustics
  • History of Physics
  • Mathematical and Statistical Physics
  • Measurement Science
  • Nuclear Physics
  • Particles and Fields
  • Plasma Physics
  • Quantum Physics
  • Relativity and Gravitation
  • Semiconductor and Mesoscopic Physics
  • Browse content in Psychology
  • Affective Sciences
  • Clinical Psychology
  • Cognitive Neuroscience
  • Cognitive Psychology
  • Criminal and Forensic Psychology
  • Developmental Psychology
  • Educational Psychology
  • Evolutionary Psychology
  • Health Psychology
  • History and Systems in Psychology
  • Music Psychology
  • Neuropsychology
  • Organizational Psychology
  • Psychological Assessment and Testing
  • Psychology of Human-Technology Interaction
  • Psychology Professional Development and Training
  • Research Methods in Psychology
  • Social Psychology
  • Browse content in Social Sciences
  • Browse content in Anthropology
  • Anthropology of Religion
  • Human Evolution
  • Medical Anthropology
  • Physical Anthropology
  • Regional Anthropology
  • Social and Cultural Anthropology
  • Theory and Practice of Anthropology
  • Browse content in Business and Management
  • Business Strategy
  • Business History
  • Business Ethics
  • Business and Government
  • Business and Technology
  • Business and the Environment
  • Comparative Management
  • Corporate Governance
  • Corporate Social Responsibility
  • Entrepreneurship
  • Health Management
  • Human Resource Management
  • Industrial and Employment Relations
  • Industry Studies
  • Information and Communication Technologies
  • International Business
  • Knowledge Management
  • Management and Management Techniques
  • Operations Management
  • Organizational Theory and Behaviour
  • Pensions and Pension Management
  • Public and Nonprofit Management
  • Strategic Management
  • Supply Chain Management
  • Browse content in Criminology and Criminal Justice
  • Criminal Justice
  • Criminology
  • Forms of Crime
  • International and Comparative Criminology
  • Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice
  • Development Studies
  • Browse content in Economics
  • Agricultural, Environmental, and Natural Resource Economics
  • Asian Economics
  • Behavioural Finance
  • Behavioural Economics and Neuroeconomics
  • Econometrics and Mathematical Economics
  • Economic Systems
  • Economic Methodology
  • Economic History
  • Economic Development and Growth
  • Financial Markets
  • Financial Institutions and Services
  • General Economics and Teaching
  • Health, Education, and Welfare
  • History of Economic Thought
  • International Economics
  • Labour and Demographic Economics
  • Law and Economics
  • Macroeconomics and Monetary Economics
  • Microeconomics
  • Public Economics
  • Urban, Rural, and Regional Economics
  • Welfare Economics
  • Browse content in Education
  • Adult Education and Continuous Learning
  • Care and Counselling of Students
  • Early Childhood and Elementary Education
  • Educational Equipment and Technology
  • Educational Strategies and Policy
  • Higher and Further Education
  • Organization and Management of Education
  • Philosophy and Theory of Education
  • Schools Studies
  • Secondary Education
  • Teaching of a Specific Subject
  • Teaching of Specific Groups and Special Educational Needs
  • Teaching Skills and Techniques
  • Browse content in Environment
  • Applied Ecology (Social Science)
  • Climate Change
  • Conservation of the Environment (Social Science)
  • Environmentalist Thought and Ideology (Social Science)
  • Natural Disasters (Environment)
  • Social Impact of Environmental Issues (Social Science)
  • Browse content in Human Geography
  • Cultural Geography
  • Economic Geography
  • Political Geography
  • Browse content in Interdisciplinary Studies
  • Communication Studies
  • Museums, Libraries, and Information Sciences
  • Browse content in Politics
  • African Politics
  • Asian Politics
  • Chinese Politics
  • Comparative Politics
  • Conflict Politics
  • Elections and Electoral Studies
  • Environmental Politics
  • European Union
  • Foreign Policy
  • Gender and Politics
  • Human Rights and Politics
  • Indian Politics
  • International Relations
  • International Organization (Politics)
  • International Political Economy
  • Irish Politics
  • Latin American Politics
  • Middle Eastern Politics
  • Political Methodology
  • Political Communication
  • Political Philosophy
  • Political Sociology
  • Political Theory
  • Political Behaviour
  • Political Economy
  • Political Institutions
  • Politics and Law
  • Public Administration
  • Public Policy
  • Quantitative Political Methodology
  • Regional Political Studies
  • Russian Politics
  • Security Studies
  • State and Local Government
  • UK Politics
  • US Politics
  • Browse content in Regional and Area Studies
  • African Studies
  • Asian Studies
  • East Asian Studies
  • Japanese Studies
  • Latin American Studies
  • Middle Eastern Studies
  • Native American Studies
  • Scottish Studies
  • Browse content in Research and Information
  • Research Methods
  • Browse content in Social Work
  • Addictions and Substance Misuse
  • Adoption and Fostering
  • Care of the Elderly
  • Child and Adolescent Social Work
  • Couple and Family Social Work
  • Developmental and Physical Disabilities Social Work
  • Direct Practice and Clinical Social Work
  • Emergency Services
  • Human Behaviour and the Social Environment
  • International and Global Issues in Social Work
  • Mental and Behavioural Health
  • Social Justice and Human Rights
  • Social Policy and Advocacy
  • Social Work and Crime and Justice
  • Social Work Macro Practice
  • Social Work Practice Settings
  • Social Work Research and Evidence-based Practice
  • Welfare and Benefit Systems
  • Browse content in Sociology
  • Childhood Studies
  • Community Development
  • Comparative and Historical Sociology
  • Economic Sociology
  • Gender and Sexuality
  • Gerontology and Ageing
  • Health, Illness, and Medicine
  • Marriage and the Family
  • Migration Studies
  • Occupations, Professions, and Work
  • Organizations
  • Population and Demography
  • Race and Ethnicity
  • Social Theory
  • Social Movements and Social Change
  • Social Research and Statistics
  • Social Stratification, Inequality, and Mobility
  • Sociology of Religion
  • Sociology of Education
  • Sport and Leisure
  • Urban and Rural Studies
  • Browse content in Warfare and Defence
  • Defence Strategy, Planning, and Research
  • Land Forces and Warfare
  • Military Administration
  • Military Life and Institutions
  • Naval Forces and Warfare
  • Other Warfare and Defence Issues
  • Peace Studies and Conflict Resolution
  • Weapons and Equipment

The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Education

  • < Previous chapter
  • Next chapter >

The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Education

26 Pragmatist Philosophy of Education

Randall Curren is Professor and Chair of Philosophy and Professor of Education at the University of Rochester. His works in philosophy of education, ethics, legal and political philosophy, and the history of philosophy include Aristotle on the Necessity of Public Education (2000). He is the editor of A Companion to the Philosophy of Education (2003) and Philosophy of Education: An Anthology (2007), and co‐editor of the journal Theory and Research in Education.

  • Published: 02 January 2010
  • Cite Icon Cite
  • Permissions Icon Permissions

This article considers pragmatic approaches to philosophy of education and philosophy. It distinguishes the philosophies of education advanced by pragmatists and evaluates the reliance of these philosophies on distinctively pragmatist methods or doctrines. It suggests that what the pragmatist vision of a science of ethics would seem to condemn most in the present landscape of philosophy of education is recourse to speculative philosophy that impairs the effectiveness of arguments for educational reform by burdening them with unnecessary and contested theoretical baggage, when what is needed is evidence and analysis.

There are different ways of doing philosophy in general, and different ways of doing philosophy of education in particular. Many are broadly analytical, in the sense that they are predicated on the idea that philosophical problems can and should be addressed at least in part through methods of logical, linguistic, epistemic, and normative analysis, including diverse and more or less formal methods of articulating the structure of theories, institutions, practices, and other objects of inquiry. Within this loosely defined analytic style of philosophy, there are countless substantive disagreements and diverse methodological standpoints on the utility and propriety of drawing on empirical research, literature, the history of philosophy, and analytical apparatus from other disciplines. This methodological diversity has many sources, including most importantly the nature of the objects of inquiry and questions at issue. Philosophy of education, being a philosophy of something, where that something is a domain of human practice , is a subfield of philosophy in which many of the questions at issue have a practical edge, and many of the most useful answers that might be given would be no less informed than philosophically adept. Abraham Edel, a pragmatist and student of John Dewey (1859–1952), argued many years ago that analytic philosophers of education should integrate “the empirical, the normative, and the contextual (especially the socio‐cultural) within the analytic method” (Edel 1973 , p. 41). 1 This has largely come to pass, though it would be overly optimistic to suppose that philosophers of education have uniformly adopted the most promising approaches characteristic of other subfields of practical philosophy.

Pragmatist philosophy and analytic philosophy are not fully disjoint forms of philosophy. There are, and have long been, analytic pragmatists, beginning with Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914), the founder of pragmatism and preeminent logician of his day, and analytic neo‐pragmatists, including Hilary Putnam ( 1995 ), Susan Haack ( 1993 ), and Robert Brandom ( 1994 , 2000 ). Varying degrees of sympathy for pragmatist ideas have been evident in instrumentalist accounts of scientific theories, deflationary theories of truth, functionalist theories of mind, and fallibilism and contextualism regarding epistemic justification, all of which have been debated in analytic philosophy for decades—so much so that one might be forgiven for thinking that the viable remains of pragmatism were long ago absorbed into the mainstream, the postphilosophical pragmatism of Richard Rorty (1931–2007) notwithstanding. 2

In the preface to their landmark Readings in Philosophical Analysis , Herbert Feigl and Wilfred Sellars acknowledged Peirce as having “more to say to us than many who are writing today” (Feigl and Sellars 1949 , p. vi). In his introduction to the volume, Feigl wrote that:

Empiricism, Skepticism, Naturalism, Positivism, and Pragmatism [disregarding some of William James's own tender‐minded deviations] are typical thought movements of the worldly, tough‐minded variety. Respect for the facts of experience, open‐mindedness, an experimental trial‐and‐error attitude, and the capacity for working within the frame of an incomplete, unfinished world view distinguish them from the more impatient, imaginative, and often aprioristic thinkers in the tender‐minded camp. (Feigl 1949 , p. 3)

Feigl wrote with regard for pragmatism as a source of the flowering of analytic philosophy, and went on to identify Peirce's pragmatic maxim as a useful formulation of the criterion of (factual) meaningfulness advocated by logical empiricists (known in the era of the Vienna Circle as logical positivists):

If we cannot possibly conceive of what would have to be the case in order to confirm or disconfirm an assertion, we would not be able to distinguish between its truth and its falsity. In that case we would simply not know what we are talking about. C. S. Peirce's pragmatic maxim, formulated in his epoch‐making essay, “How to Make Our Ideas Clear,” has essentially the same import.… If and only if assertion and denial of a sentence imply a difference capable of observational (experiential, operational, or experimental) test, does the sentence have factual meaning. (Feigl 1949 , p. 9)

In the paper Feigl refers to, Peirce presents his pragmatic analysis of meaning as an alternative to the Cartesian standard of clear and distinct ideas , and aims to chasten metaphysics and apriorism in much the way that other empiricists have (see Kloesel 1986 , p. 257 ff ). Years later, in “What Pragmatism Is,” he refers to himself as a positivist and leaves no doubt as to why:

[Pragmatic analysis] will serve to show that almost every proposition of ontological metaphysics is either meaningless gibberish…or else is downright absurd; so that all such rubbish being swept away, what will remain of philosophy will be a series of problems capable of investigation by the observational methods of the true sciences. (Peirce 1905 , p. 171)

Bertrand Russell's announcement of a parallel assault on misguided metaphysics, in “On Denoting,” would strike many as tame by comparison (Russell 1905 ). 3

If pragmatist philosophy and analytic philosophy have shared considerable common ground, it is nevertheless true that the pragmatist and analytic movements have had different and distinctive histories. Most obviously, pragmatism was in the early decades of the twentieth century a widely discussed public philosophy, allied with the progressive and legal realism reform movements, and engaged with matters of urgent social and political concern. 4 Crucial to this was a rejection of a priori endorsements of universal principles or values, and a meliorist or reform‐minded embrace of an evolutionary and experimentalist conception of social, political, and legal institutions. 5 The adequacy of institutions would be judged on the basis of their consequences in the existing social context. Through decades in which analytic philosophy was precluded from social commentary by its epistemological focus and meta‐ethical noncognitivism—that is, the view that moral judgments are devoid of propositional content—pragmatism about values was understood to entail a kind of progressive cognitivism that preserved a role for philosophy in reasoned social criticism. Most important for our purposes here, pragmatism was closely associated with American philosophy of education through much of the twentieth century, owing very much to the dominating influence of John Dewey.

The main questions to be addressed here are: What distinguishes the philosophies of education advanced by pragmatists? What reliance do these philosophies place on distinctively pragmatist methods or doctrines? Does pragmatism have something distinctive to offer contemporary philosophy of education?

1. Pragmatism: Meaning, Truth, and Inquiry

Pragmatism was conceived at the “Metaphysical Club,” where Peirce first presented his pragmatic maxim, in Cambridge, Massachusetts, in the 1870s. The group that convened philosophical discussions there included William James, the mathematician Chauncey Wright, Oliver Wendell Holmes and two other lawyers, the historian John Fisk, and the “scientific theist” Francis Abbott. The evolution studies of Charles Darwin and the empiricism of John Stuart Mill were influential in this group through Wright, who was himself known to Darwin for his work on evolutionary adaptation in plants (Wiener 1949 , p. 31).

Peirce brought to this group the perspective of a chemist, physicist, mathematician, and logician, and formulated his maxim in a way that spanned matters of fact or experimental methods, relations of ideas or formal systems, and human practices broadly. He began from Alexander Bain's definition of belief as a disposition to act or “rule for action,” which suggested to him the fundamental pragmatist doctrine that thought (“rational cognition”) and action (“rational purpose”) are in some sense inseparable. 6 Embedding this in a hard‐nosed naturalism about human nature, which accepted the fact of biological, social, and institutional evolution, he and his pragmatist followers came to regard thought and ideas as instrumental and properly measured by instrumental success. This was understood in a way consistent with an embrace of experimental empiricism in science and human affairs, and an understanding of axioms through their deductive consequences in formal systems. Empirical hypotheses have observational consequences, legal rules and institutional policies have consequences for human well‐being, and mathematical and logical propositions have inferential consequences. Peirce's pragmatic maxim treats these consequences as not only the measure but also the meaning (and limits of meaning ) of the hypotheses or beliefs in question. If a belief is a behavioral disposition or habit, what could a belief's content consist of but the hypothesis that certain consequences would accompany the believer's actions in the various circumstances that could arise? An assertion without discernible consequences through which it could be tested would be empty words.

Axioms implicitly defined within their systems in this way lose any claim to a priori synthetic (descriptive) certainty, as those of Euclidean geometry did when geometries grounded in alternative axioms were invented. Governments and their laws lose any claim to self‐evident authority. Science, which might have been thought to rest on unshakeable certainties, is seen to be the experimental and fallible enterprise that it is. This realism about the sciences did not diminish it in the eyes of the pragmatists, despite the conclusions Peirce drew in applying his account of belief and meaning to the nature of truth and reality. Let us note his formulation of the account in “How to Make our Ideas Clear,” and trace its application to judgments of truth and reality:

[T]he whole function of thought is to produce habits of action.… What the habit is depends on when and how it causes us to act. As for when , every stimulus to action is derived from perception; as for the how , every purpose of action is to produce some sensible result. Thus, we come down to what is tangible and practical, as the root of every real distinction of thought, no matter how subtile it may be; and there is no distinction of meaning so fine as to consist in anything but a possible difference of practice. (Kloesel 1986 , p. 265)

Consider, then, my belief that the loaf I've baked is smaller than a breadbox, and my related belief that a breadbox is a good place to store bread. What do these beliefs come to, according to Peirce? Most obviously, that I may try to place the loaf in a breadbox, if I have one at hand, expecting to see that the loaf will fit inside with the box closed, and expecting to find that if I return a day, or two, or three later, and feel and taste the bread, that I will find it not unpleasantly stale or nibbled by mice, but wholesome and intact. Less obviously, the belief that the loaf is smaller than a breadbox would entail expectations about what I would observe if I set about measuring the two—expectations about the possibility of finding a container into which the loaf would fit but the breadbox would not, and so on. The meaning of a belief is in this way cashed out as a function of possible actions and anticipated outcomes.

What happens when one subjects assertions about truth and reality to pragmatic analysis? If beliefs about truth have any meaning, it would be because they, too, are testable, and their meaning would be reducible in some sense to the methods and consequences by which they are tested. However, testing the belief, “It is true that p ” would seem to be no different from testing p itself. Faced with this, one could regard assertions of truth as redundant or devise some other deflationary or metaphysically cautious account of the language of truth. Peirce holds, rather more contentiously, that “the ideas of truth and falsehood, in their full development, appertain exclusively to the scientific method of settling opinion” (Kloesel 1986 , p. 272). He then holds that:

[T]he processes of investigation, if only pushed far enough, will give one certain solution to every question to which they can be applied.… Different minds may set out with the most antagonistic views, but the progress of investigation carries them by a force outside themselves to one and the same conclusion. This great law is embodied in the conception of truth and reality. The opinion which is fated to be ultimately agreed to by all who investigate, is what we mean by the truth, and the object represented in this opinion is the real. (p. 273)

It is in this way that truth and reality come to be defined by pragmatists in terms of agreement within a community of inquiry, but it need not have been so. The conclusion is a semantic analysis of the terms “true” and “real,” and it is not entailed by Peirce's pragmatic maxim, or even the conjunction of the maxim and his “great law” concerning the eventual convergence of scientific opinion. 7

It is the pragmatic method of analysis that Peirce and James both identify as the heart of pragmatism, so much so that Dewey remarked that in reading Pragmatism (James 1907 ), “one frequently gets the impression that he conceives the discussion of the other two points [the nature of ideas and truth; the nature of reality] to be illustrative material, more or less hypothetical, of the method” (Dewey 1908/1990 , p. 377). The method, James says, is “The attitude of looking away from first things, principles, ‘categories,’ supposed necessities; and of looking towards last things, fruits, consequences, facts” (James 1907 , pp. 54–55). It is a “method” much in harmony with earlier forms of empiricism, and distinguished from them primarily by the insistence that knowledge is a product not of passive perception, but of active interventions in the world that leave a mark on it.

In this brief introduction to pragmatism, we find five elements that became recurrent themes of the movement: (1) a rejection of apriorism and certainty, and a corresponding embrace of fallibilism, empirical and experimental methods, and the ideal of a community of scientific inquiry; (2) a naturalistic and evolutionary perspective on reality in general and human nature in particular; (3) an associated instrumentalism about thought, language, knowledge, values, and institutions; (4) an associated account of meaning, deployed as a tool of philosophical analysis, in the form of the pragmatic maxim; (5) accounts of truth and reality as products of inquiry.

To these we may now add, with qualification: (6) a commitment to secular democratic individualism or liberal democracy. Although James had pronounced democratic sympathies, the same could not be said of his European followers (Wiener 1973 ). Moreover, there is nothing in the five primary elements of pragmatism that would compel an embrace of democracy; nothing that would preclude a naturalistic, evolutionary, instrumentalist embrace of a quite undemocratic Social Darwinism, or Social Spencerism, as some would have it. 8 The social “Darwinist,” Herbert Spencer, defined the pedagogical doctrines of progressive education more than anyone else (Cremin 1961 , p. 91; Egan 2002 ), and it is far from evident that the adoption of pragmatist commitments would have given him any reason to revise his social and political views. An instrumentalist or consequentialist view of institutions becomes progressive in an egalitarian or social democratic way only if one adopts an egalitarian view of what kinds of consequences matter. Dewey did just that in adopting an egalitarian and eudaimonistic form of consequentialism, a liberal individualist vision of social experimentation as a vehicle of individual flourishing and social progress, and an associated developmental conception of democracy (Dewey 1916 , 1939/1989 ; Gouinlock 1986 ; Held 1987 , pp. 85–104; Campbell 1995 ). Dewey conceived of democracy as a form of social life in which “cooperative intelligence” can freely operate through social experimentation and progressive adjustments of goals and policies in light of collective deliberation grounded in the experience of every member of society. It is the form of social life that provides the best setting for continued individual “growth”—for the “liberation of powers,” yielding “a progressive growth directed to social aims”—according to Dewey, and he proposed the same test of adequacy for other institutions, including schools (Dewey 1916 ). 9 In this vision, the empirical spirit of pragmatism is tethered to democracy through a conception of the processes of democratic social life modeled on the norms of a scientific community, and the idea that participation in those norms is conducive to personal growth. Though not quite inevitable, the union endured and commitment to democracy became a staple of American pragmatism.

2. James, Dewey, and the Philosophy of Education

It is in the work of William James that we first encounter a semblance of what might be thought of as a pragmatist philosophy of education. James was induced to deliver a series of lectures to the teachers of Cambridge, Massachusetts, in 1892, and these appeared together as his Talks to Teachers on Psychology in 1899. Elements of pragmatism had been evident in his writings on cognition as early as 1885, and one sees some evidence of pragmatist ideas in these lectures, though one also finds elements of the educational ideas of Locke and Spencer. Although the originating premise of the lectures is that they would draw pedagogical lessons from James's monumental Principles of Psychology (James 1890/1983 ), he remarks in the opening lecture that “there is no ‘new psychology’ worthy of the name. There is nothing but the old psychology which began in Locke's time, plus a little physiology of the brain and senses and theory of evolution, and a few refinements of introspective detail” (James 1901 , p. 15).

Pragmatist ideas are most evident in the lectures on “The Child as a Behaving Organism,” “Education and Behavior,” and “Native Reactions and Acquired Reactions,” where James asserts that the stream of consciousness that fills our waking hours has the primary function of producing action. “[M]an,” he says, “is primarily a practical being, whose mind is given to him to aid in adapting him to this world's life” (James 1901 , p. 24). He argues that this view of the mind has the virtue of being most consistent with the physiology of the brain and an evolutionary view of our place in the animal kingdom. It follows that education is “the organizing of resources in the human being, or powers of conduct which shall fit him to his social and physical world,” or, more simply, “ the organization of acquired habits of conduct and tendencies to behavior ” (p. 27). By way of illustration, James describes the child's “training in good manners” (pp. 34–35) and cites the educational ideal of the German universities of his time: to turn men into “efficient instrument[s] of research” (p. 28).

The limitations of this instrumentalism about the mental life and its training are especially apparent in the lecture on the acquisition of ideas, which James describes as “inner objects of contemplation,” gathered in experiences, and abstracted and grasped in relation to one another by the mind (pp. 88–89). Education is said to “fill the mind little by little, as experiences accrete, with a stock of such ideas” (p. 88), and an educated mind is said to be “the mind which has the largest stock of them, ready to meet the largest possible variety of the emergencies of life” (p. 89). Advice for teachers enters with the suggestion that children are disposed to assimilate different kinds of ideas at different ages: “sensible properties of material things” during the first seven or eight years of life, and only later in adolescence “the more abstract aspects of experience,” such as the sciences and “moral relations” (pp. 89–90). James borrows from Herbert Spencer—and, broadly speaking, Jean‐Jacques Rousseau—in encouraging the teacher to “feed” the growing mind what it “shows a natural craving” for at each age (p. 90)—namely, activities of making and doing to develop knowledge of the “material world” in the early years, and “verbal material” or “verbal reproduction” after the onset of adolescence “even in the natural sciences, so far as these are causal and rational, and not merely confined to description” (p. 91).

To his credit, James criticizes progressive educators who would too long immerse children in hand work, keeping them from the more abstract studies “the mind craves” (p. 92), but there is much in this little lecture and its companions to disappoint and lower expectations about the educational import of pragmatism. The conception of the natural sciences and how to teach them is not recognizably that of a pragmatist, who might be expected to display some enthusiasm for experimental methods, and rather less enthusiasm for “verbal reproduction.” The account of learning stages is an echo of Spencer's immensely influential principle of putting the concrete before the abstract, the empirical before the rational (see Egan 2002 , esp. pp. 18–19). The narrowness of its vision of what is learned in the early years—“sensible properties of material things”—is remarkable, and barely comprehensible except as a reflection of Locke's account of simple ideas as the building blocks of all knowledge. 10 If anything, James's view exhibits less of the pragmatist's characteristic focus on conduct than Rousseau's stage theory. In Rousseau's version the stages are not defined by the acquisition of concrete or empirical ideas versus abstract or rational ideas, but by a series of forms of motivation: the child is first moved by pleasure and pain, later by consideration of what is useful in achieving chosen ends, and finally by a consideration of what is right and wrong. All told, it would be an immense stretch to find a pragmatist philosophy of education in James's Talks to Teachers . The little work expected of pragmatism yields barely more than an abstract characterization of education as training calculated to produce desirable habits.

The image of a characteristically pragmatist philosophy of education—an image well entrenched through the later twentieth century—is predicated almost entirely on Dewey's philosophy of education. 11

Dewey's philosophy of education is shaped by three fundamental commitments: a naturalistic and evolutionary conception of human nature and human affairs; a high regard for the methods and norms of experimental, scientific inquiry; and a conception of democracy as a form of social life consistent with individual growth, experimentation with new social forms, and collective control of society's evolution. Building on prior developments in pragmatism, Dewey regards mind as a function of a complex organism and ideas as tools that facilitate human activity and the management of experience (Dewey 1910/1978 , 1925/1958 ). The various further products of mind, including languages, theories, institutions, cultures, and the personalities that presuppose all of these, are similarly tools or instruments grounded in the biological nature of human beings, equipping us to better manage what we experience, and to exercise further control of ourselves and the development of our societies. Our freedom owes much more to the cultural resources that enable us to evaluate, define, and direct our actions than to any natural gifts we might have. Philosophy, being a product of mind and cultural resource of the kind in question, is understood to be a tool for examining how we think, for furthering our development, and for responding to the public's problems and advancing the work of social reconstruction. Education, broadly construed, is the means through which such tools of inquiry and growth are disseminated, and it is for this reason the most fundamental vehicle of social reconstruction. In this scheme, philosophy becomes both an educative endeavor and one to which philosophy of education is central. It is also a scheme in which the methods of philosophy of education become at least in part experimental , as Dewey's did through the operation of his Laboratory School at the University of Chicago. The results of the experiments conducted there contributed to such publications as My Pedagogic Creed ( 1897/1972 ), The School and Society ( 1900 ), and The Child and the Curriculum ( 1902 ).

If the influence of Peirce's conception of philosophy is apparent here—his view that “what will remain of philosophy will be a series of problems capable of investigation by the methods of the true sciences”—his conceptions of thinking and inquiry are similarly apparent in Dewey's account of the nature of (effective) inquiry presented in How We Think ( 1910/1978 ). According to this account, effective thinking or inquiry can be analyzed as a five‐part sequence. We (1) begin from an emotional response to an unsettling situation, (2) move on to an intellectual response, (3) generate a hypothesis that promises a resolution of the felt tension, (4) examine the hypothesis by reasoning and identification of consequences that flow from it, and finally (5) test the hypothesis empirically by arranging to observe whether the anticipated consequences actually occur. Dewey understood this experimentalist account of thinking to apply to the examination of value as well as more obviously testable matters. He held that one participates in a kind of character education in learning the norms of inquiry that regulate effective thinking and the behavior of scientific communities, and in submitting to those norms in the process of testing forms of conduct and coming to understand their consequences.

In light of this account of effective thinking and associated notion of character formation, Dewey holds that an educational institution is one in which individuals learn and use the skills of experimental inquiry, observing the norms of open communication characteristic of scientific communities. These norms include:

willingness to hold belief in suspense, ability to doubt until evidence is obtained; willingness to go where evidence points instead of putting first a personally preferred conclusion; ability to hold ideas in solution and use them as hypotheses to be tested instead of as dogmas to be asserted; and (possibly the most distinctive of all) enjoyment of new fields for inquiry and of new problems. (Dewey 1939/1989 , p. 112)

In schools, this implies engaging students in developing both the skills and the attitudes essential to scientific inquiry, which are necessarily exercised in the context of a community of inquiry . Science is not a solitary affair, but one essentially involving cooperation with other investigators, who ideally observe not only the norms noted above but also those pertaining to honest, respectful, and intelligent dialogue. Dewey holds that classrooms should themselves be communities of inquiry in which students will come to exhibit the requisite skills and virtues. He also holds that this is essential to individual growth, or open‐ended, self‐directed development—holding out “growth” in this sense as an ideal compatible with Darwinian evolution, unlike the Aristotelian ideal of flourishing, which involves the idea of fulfilling the potential entailed by a fixed species‐essence. He further insists that this is vital to democracy: “Until what shall be taught and how it is taught is settled upon the basis of formation of the scientific attitude, the so‐called educational work of schools is a dangerously hit‐or‐miss affair as far as democracy is concerned” (Dewey 1939/1989 , p. 115).

What democracy requires above all is improving the quality of public discourse, and seeing that the free flow of information is not impeded by divisions of class, occupation, or sect, so that society itself operates according to the norms of scientific inquiry. Operating in this way, it becomes a mode of social organization conducive to the growth of its members, as well as effective in pursuing public projects and “flexible readjustment of its institutions” through cooperative inquiry and social experiments (Dewey 1916 , p. 99). Put somewhat differently, democracy as Dewey conceives it would provide individuals with a basis for controlling their own development, and provide societies with the means to collectively control their own evolution. The requisite “freer interaction between social groups” (p. 86) was pursued by Jane Addams and other participants in the progressive social settlement movement, which allowed people of diverse fortunes to live in close proximity, learning from each other and pursuing common projects. Engaging diverse students in working together in schools was similarly a goal for schools. Dewey argued that the separation of vocational and academic education, the former producing “mere skill in production” and the latter “a knowledge that is an ornament and a cultural embellishment,” must be eliminated in favor of “a course of study which should be useful and liberal at the same time” (pp. 256, 258). 12 He also argued strongly for co‐education of males and females, and opposed the splitting off of religious communities into separate schools.

In applying these ideas, Dewey took the problems of education in the formative years of the American public school system as a point of departure. These included the loss of opportunities for informal education associated with industrialization, new mass media that made it easier to saturate the public with propaganda, and the rapid evolution of society that threatened to make current ideas and skills obsolete. The first problem was to be addressed, along with other pervasive shortcomings of traditional schools, by eliminating the separation of schooling and life. Dewey held that learning, which is functional and thus highly motivated in life, can be made much more so in schools with the right combination of “child‐centered” observance of natural forms of learning and “teacher‐centered” selection of curricula responsive to student needs and interests. This would require the elimination of drilling and other forms of information delivery that fail to engage students in active inquiry, and the elimination of narrow vocational training, in favor of forms of inquiry learning that combine practical and academic components. The third problem is also largely addressed through these means, since no one would be consigned to a narrow curriculum of manual skills that could easily become obsolete. Everyone would learn the skills of experimental inquiry and the critical and reflective skills and attitudes those entail, and they would be taught to grow and continually adapt. The second problem would also be addressed through the development of these skills, which Dewey took to be essential to robust public debate, and through eliminating the authoritarian management of classrooms, which invited passivity and conformity. Cooperative inquiry would henceforth be encouraged, instead of suppressed as a form of cheating, and cooperation with the school's purposes would be achieved largely through voluntary acceptance of the norms of activities gladly engaged in.

Writing in 1938, Dewey surveyed the trajectory of the progressive education movement and took some pains to distinguish his own educational vision from both progressive and “traditional” schooling. At its core, progressive education holds that schools should educate the “whole child” through methods that allow learning to occur in accordance with natural patterns of learning, which is to say in a natural sequence and manner, and motivated and guided by the child's natural desire to learn (Zilversmit 1993 , p. 18). Dewey shared much of the progressive embrace of natural patterns of learning, but insisted that teachers still have a role to play in selecting curricula and establishing classroom norms of inquiry and cooperation (Dewey 1938 ). The shared commitments are evident in Dewey's desire to diminish the separation of learning from life, of academics from self‐directed activity; in his embrace of learning through inquiry; in the room he leaves for child‐directed learning; and in his endorsements of the basic progressive, Spencerian, and Rousseauian principle that the educator “has to find ways of doing consciously and deliberately what ‘nature’ accomplishes in the early years” (Dewey 1938 , p. 74).

3. Pragmatist Philosophy of Education in Extremis

Dewey's educational ideas remain influential at several foci of advocacy, including the community of inquiry and cooperative learning models (Lipman 2003 ; Slavin 1995 ), Lawrence Kohlberg's just community model of moral education (Power, Higgins, and Kohlberg 1989 ), and various related models of classroom management and discipline. More generally, it is no exaggeration to say that progressive educational ideas can be counted on to reassert themselves as new and revolutionary every few years, as the insistence on the naturalness of basing literacy instruction on “whole language” has done for at least a century and a half now.

Setting aside the enduring influence of Dewey's philosophy of education, and the educational ideas of the progressive movement, there remains the question of whether there is a distinctively pragmatist approach to philosophy of education.

Let us note, first, that in the survey just concluded we found little evidence of the pragmatist method of analysis, embodied in the pragmatic maxim , playing any role in producing substantial results in philosophy of education. We saw it deployed in James's lectures to little effect, and we can reasonably ask whether an unflinching deployment of it would not suggest most obviously a form of behaviorism . Peirce offered a variety of formulations of his basic conception of meaning, but the one announced in “How to Make Our Ideas Clear” is exhibited in dispositional analyses of traits such as hardness. Applied to persons, this yields logical behaviorism, or the view that mental attributes are behavioral dispositions. E. L. Thorndike, a student of James's and colleague of Dewey's, endorsed the latter's instrumentalism and developed the theory of operant or instrumental conditioning, later reworked by B. F. Skinner. The prospects along this path are no longer inviting, and it is not surprising that philosophers of education sympathetic to pragmatism now repudiate them. 13 The application of Peirce's method of analysis to formal systems lends support to a different kind of mental functionalism, also embraced by logical empiricists and computational modelers, as well as pragmatists or pragmatic sympathizers such as Sellars and Brandom. Regarding the terms in a formal system as implicitly defined within the system ( a la Peirce), one can model beliefs and other mental items as defined by functional roles in a “system” that explains what a person does. There is a more generous conception of empirical significance at work here, and it is certainly progress to abandon logical behaviorism in favor of cognitive models, but at this level of abstraction we are still very far from doing philosophy of education.

Suppose we regard pragmatism not as a method of analysis, as Peirce and James did, but as a philosophical orientation defined (as it was at the end of section I) by experimentalism, evolutionary naturalism, instrumentalism, and pragmatist theories of meaning, truth, and reality. Would this yield Dewey's philosophy of education, or might it just as readily lend itself to a behaviorist view of education? The answer, surely, is that it requires a great deal of selectivity and oversight to accept Dewey's philosophy of education as the essence of what pragmatism yields in the domain of philosophy of education. It is organized around some pragmatist themes, but it would be quite a leap to regard it as typical of what one could construct from pragmatist starting points. It does not depend fundamentally on any distinctively pragmatist doctrines, and it does depend on a good deal that is not essentially pragmatist—above all, the legacy of Rousseau, filtered through a tradition of pedagogical experiments and the writings of Spencer.

Reviewing the canonical elements of pragmatism, and allowing the addition of democracy, those that are evident in Dewey's educational thought are: (1) an embrace of experimental science; (2) a naturalistic view of human nature; (3) an embrace of democracy. What is noteworthy about these commitments is that they are now so widely shared that holding them does not mark one as a pragmatist. The early pragmatists were among the revolutionaries who adopted a broadly naturalistic, scientific, and (sometimes) liberal democratic outlook, but they were not the only ones, and we are now nearly all naturalists and democrats. Most of us accept the fact of evolution, though we may doubt that the transient existence of species has the revolutionary implications for philosophical methodology that Dewey supposed. Most of us are advocates of secular liberal democracy, though we may not favor Dewey's particular conception of democracy as a form of society modeled on scientific communities. We all accept that cognition is embodied and situated—that bodies and societies provide contexts for thinking and learning. 14 Whatever we think about science, we are all or nearly all fallibilists. It is thus hard to see anything distinctively pragmatist in a commitment to Dewey's starting points. By contrast, the doctrines that do remain distinctively pragmatist—such as Dewey's insistence that inquiry does not reveal an independently existing world, but instead alters and makes it what it is in the interaction—play no significant role in his philosophy of education.

There continue to be advocates of pragmatism in philosophy of education, but it is debatable whether they have absorbed the basic pragmatist message about how to do philosophy any more than other philosophers of education have. It is not unusual for contemporary neo‐pragmatists or pragmatist sympathizers in educational theory to echo Dewey's themes—the misbegotten quest for certainty, misguided authoritarianism in classroom management, learning through inquiry, art in the education of the whole person, and the wisdom of abjuring fixed ends in education—yet to do this without particular attention to the empirical methods, context, and consequences recommended by pragmatism. What distinguishes neo‐pragmatism in philosophy of education today is not its practical edge but its recourse to pragmatist sources and an associated and problematic embrace of systematic philosophy as the key to doing deep or truly philosophical practical philosophy (see, e.g., Arcilla 1995 ; Burbules 1995 ; Neiman 1995 ; Standish 2003 ). Misbegotten attempts to glean educational lessons from metaphysics and epistemology are not the exclusive province of neo‐pragmatism, but the underlying methodological tendency has surely been encouraged by an exaggerated estimation of the extent to which Dewey simply applied pragmatism to education. 15

Several decades ago, analytic philosophers became impatient with the state of meta‐ethics and the obstacle it posed to philosophical engagement with practical affairs. Some dove directly into analytical engagement with practical issues, some turned to work in normative ethical and political theory more or less engaged with applications, and others made new attempts within meta‐ethics to find a rational basis for regarding morality as reason‐giving. These developments gave rise to a variety of ways of pursuing engaged ethical, social, legal, political, and educational philosophy, more or less grounded in systematic analyses of such concepts as desert, well‐being, and integrity, more or less grounded in normative theories of ethics and justice, and more or less systematically grounded in relevant empirical sources. The pragmatist focus on context and consequences in evaluating institutions, laws, and policies is not inconsistent with such approaches to practical philosophy, provided they are indeed serious about getting the facts right and do not ignore the current common wisdom in moral theory that consequences matter. If my characterization of the patterns of contemporary neo‐pragmatism in philosophy of education are correct, then it follows that to the extent contemporary analytic philosophers of education adhere to Edel's advice to integrate “the empirical, the normative, and the contextual (especially the socio‐cultural) within the analytic method” (Edel 1973 , p. 41), it is within analytic philosophy that the basic pragmatist message about how to do philosophy of education lives on. This is no longer Dewey's “time when America was still a symbol of the dawn of a better day and was full of hope infused with courage,” but it is within the vigorous and informed debates of analytical liberalism, cast in terms fit for a wider public and policy arena, that there is promise of something reaching “beyond the confines of technical philosophy” (Dewey 1949 , p. xiv).

What the pragmatist vision of a science of ethics would seem to condemn most in the present landscape of philosophy of education is recourse to speculative philosophy that impairs the effectiveness of arguments for educational reform by burdening them with unnecessary and contested theoretical baggage, when what is needed is evidence and analysis. It is hard to imagine that, in the circumstances we face today, Dewey would have prized the transmission of his ideas, or attempts to find some educational import in contemporary pragmatist theories, over direct normative investigations of corporate influences in schools (Brighouse 2007 ), racially integrated schooling (Blum 2007 ), or interventions to prevent forced marriages of school age girls (McAvoy 2008 ). 16 If philosophy is a tool, then let it be sharp and efficient in cutting to the chase.

I owe thanks to John Bennett, Robert Holmes, and Harvey Siegel for helpful comments on a penultimate draft of this chapter.

Edel (1908–2007) was a doctoral student in philosophy at Columbia University in the 1930s, during the final years of John Dewey's teaching career there. His book Ethical Judgment: The Use of Science in Ethics ( 1955 ) is characteristic of pragmatist ethical theory, in its regard for morality as a human product in a contingent and changing world, and its view that a priori absolutes must be set aside and everything tested by experience, using science and its methods.

See Rorty 1979 , 1991 . Some accounts of the nature of pragmatism find a cleavage between reform and revolutionary pragmatism, and see little plausibility in Rorty's attempts to claim the authority of those in the former camp for his own revolutionary variety. See Migotti 1988 ; Haack 1996 ; and Mounce 1997 . The earliest pragmatists, Peirce and William James (1842–1910), regarded pragmatism as an analytical methodology, not a substantive philosophy, but their views differed in ways that gave rise to more or less revolutionary doctrines within pragmatism, with the revolutionary elements descending from James and his disciple, the English literary humanist Ferdinand (F. C. S.) Schiller (1864–1937).

For further discussion of the similarities and connections between pragmatism and logical empiricism and positivism, see Wiener 1973 . Morton White details the “scientific outlook” shared by Dewey, Oliver Wendell Holmes (1841–1935), and other pragmatists, and refers to the writings of positivists and operationalists as “half‐critical, half‐supporting” (White 1947 , p. 5). For good general histories of pragmatism, see Wiener 1949 and Thayer 1968 .

In addition to progressive education and progressive law, the movement embraced “social settlement” in distressed communities as a form of direct action to facilitate social improvement. See Addams 1902/2002 , 1910/1990 ; Deegan 1988 .

On the hostility of progressive reform theorists to abstract principles and “formalism,” see White 1947 . “Formalism,” as White describes it, is in many respects the very foe attacked by pragmatists: an outlook that treats logic, deduction, and a priori principles as a substitute for experience, historical understanding, and an application of scientific methods. The reform‐minded legal realists of the early twentieth century adopted characteristic pragmatist stances in: (1) criticizing legal principles of the nineteenth century, for their insensitivity to contemporary conditions and for being barriers to social progress; (2) holding that the meaning of legal rules or principles is determined, not by their intuitive moral content or derivation from higher principles, but by the practice and consequences of applying them. See Pound 1910 , 1911 ; Llewellyn 1930 . Industrialization and consequent changes in the nature of employment had, in fact, profoundly altered the kinds of cases coming before courts and the relationships between the litigants, with the result that principles designed for accidents between strangers frequently produced devastating outcomes for workers. A good example of this was the application of the principle of contributory negligence to disabling injuries arising from workplace hazards. Workers who had complained of hazards that were not their fault, not remedied, and from which they suffered were denied compensation on the grounds they were aware of the hazards and chose to stay on the job, thereby exposing themselves to the risks that eventuated in their injuries. For documentation of this and other examples, see White 1980 . Holmes, though very much a pragmatist in his analysis of law (Holmes 1881 ), did not join the ranks of the reformers until his famous dissent in Lochner v . New York , a 1905 decision that, in the name of freedom of contract, struck down a law limiting the work week of bakers to 64 hours.

Peirce referred to Bain as the “Scottish ancestor of pragmatism” (Wiener 1949 , p. 68). Focusing on pragmatism as a tradition of American cultural criticism, one might identify Ralph Waldo Emerson as another “grandfather” of the movement (West 1989 ).

Nor does anything follow about the nature of truth from the defeasibility of evidence , the proposition that evidence is never so conclusive as to produce certainty. All that follows from defeasibility is that we can't be absolutely certain of the truth of what we assert. It is often held (by nonphilosophers) that philosophers have shown that nothing is absolutely certain—that it is always possible that new evidence may force us to revise our beliefs—and it is just as often held that it follows from this that there is no “absolute truth.” This is a non sequitur , and it lends nothing but obscurity to the issue to append the qualifier “absolute” to “truth.”

Herbert Spencer used the expression “survival of the fittest” before and more persistently than Darwin did, and unlike Darwin he used it in opposing public schools and defending ruthless capitalist exploitation of the poor. His conception of adaptation was Lamarckian, moreover, so it is doubly unjust to call the repugnant view he popularized “Social Darwinism” (see Egan 2002 , pp. 23 ff ).

The reference to individual powers being both liberated and directed to social aims signifies a fusion in Dewey's thought of the individualistic liberty of Mill with a more collectivist Hegelian notion of freedom as voluntary constraint by the norms of cooperative endeavors.

Spencer's principle seems to be a crude application of the Lockean premise that simple ideas must be gathered through experience before the mind can work upon them to produce “conceptions of a higher and more abstract order,” as James so succinctly puts it (James 1901/1983 , p. 89).

One may credit Dewey's collaborator, George Herbert Mead (1863–1931), and his various intellectual descendants, with secondary roles.

Morton White finds evidence of a direct influence of Thorstein Veblen's Theory of the Leisure Class ( 1899 ) in Dewey's appraisal of ornamental learning (White 1947 , p. 98).

Jim Garrison and Alven Neiman may be right in saying that “Thorndike's victory internationally is one of the major reasons most educators completely ignore pragmatism,” but they give no indication of recognizing the extent to which Thorndike's behaviorism embodies a pragmatist approach (Garrison and Neiman 2003 , p. 26).

It is worth noting that pragmatists err in assuming that Descartes' mind‐body dualism precludes a role for the body in the affairs of the mind. See Schmitter, Tarcov and, Donner 2003 , pp. 78–79, and related references.

In the 1960s, when analytic philosophy of education was getting under way, Harper & Row launched The Philosophy of Education Series, consisting of texts “furnish[ing] authentic presentations of major contemporary philosophies as they relate to, or impinge upon, educational practice” (Bayles 1966 , p. x). The series began with a volume on pragmatism by the series editor, and included others on idealism, existentialism, and realism. Philosophers of education look back in horror on the age of “isms,” but the assumption that one can find educational “applications” in just about any work of philosophy has been harder to shake.

For commentary on a recent attempt to find educational import in Brandom's inferentialist pragmatism, see Curren 2008 .

Addams, Jane . ( 1902 /2002). Democracy and Social Ethics. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.

Google Scholar

Google Preview

—— ( 1910 /1990). Twenty Years at Hull House. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.

Arcilla, René . ( 1995 ). For the Love of Perfection: Richard Rorty and Liberal Education. London: Routledge.

Bayles, Ernest . ( 1966 ). Pragmatism in Education . New York: Harper & Row.

Blum, Lawrence . ( 2007 ). “The Promise of Racial Integration in a Multicultural Age.” In Philosophy of Education: An Anthology , ed. Randall Curren (pp. 266–82). Oxford: Blackwell.

Brandom, Robert . ( 1994 ). Making it Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

—— ( 2000 ). Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Brighouse, Harry . ( 2007 ). “Channel One, the Anti‐Commercial Principle, and the Discontinuous Ethos.” In Philosophy of Education: An Anthology , ed. Randall Curren (pp. 208–20). Oxford: Blackwell.

Burbules, Nicholas . ( 1995 ). “Authority and the Tragic Dimension of Teaching.” In The Educational Conversation: Closing the Gap , ed. J. Garrison and A. G. Rud Jr. (pp. 29–40). Albany: State University of New York Press.

Campbell, James . ( 1995 ). Understanding John Dewey. Chicago: Open Court.

Cremin, Lawrence . ( 1961 ). The Transformation of the School: Progressivism in American Education, 1876–1957. New York: Knopf.

Curren, Randall , ed. ( 2007 ). Philosophy of Education: An Anthology . Oxford: Blackwell.

—— ( 2008 ). “Inferentialism Goes to School.” In Philosophy of Education 2007 , ed. B. Stengel (pp. 125–27). Urbana, IL: Philosophy of Education Society.

Deegan, Mary Jo. ( 1988 ). Jane Addams and the Men of the Chicago School, 1892–1918 . New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Books.

Dewey, John . ( 1897 /1972). My Pedagogic Creed. In Early Works of John Dewey, 1882–1898, vol. 5: 1895–1898 , ed. J. A. Boydston (pp. 84–95). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

—— ( 1900 ). The School and Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

—— ( 1902 ). The Child and the Curriculum . Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

—— ( 1908 /1998). “What Pragmatism Means by ‘Practical’.” In The Essential Dewey, Vol. 2: Ethics, Logic, Psychology , ed. L. Hickman and L. Alexander (pp. 377–86). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

—— ( 1910 /1978). How We Think. In The Middle Works, 1899–1924, Vol. 6: 1910–1911 , ed. J. A. Boydston (pp. 177–355). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press. 10.1037/10903-000

—— ( 1916 ). Democracy and Education. New York: Macmillan.

—— ( 1925 /1958). Experience and Nature . New York: Dover.

—— ( 1929 ). The Quest for Certainty. New York: Minton, Balch.

—— ( 1938 ). Experience and Education. New York: Collier.

—— ( 1939 /1989). Freedom and Culture . Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books.

—— ( 1949 ). Foreword. In Evolution and the Founders of Pragmatism , by Philip P. Wiener (pp. xiii–xiv). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Edel, Abraham . ( 1955 ). Ethical Judgment: The Use of Science in Ethics . Glencoe, IL: Free Press.

—— ( 1973 ). “Analytic Philosophy of Education at the Crossroads.” In Educational Judgments , ed. James Doyle (pp. 232–57). London: Routledge.

Egan, Kieran . ( 2002 ). Getting It Wrong from the Beginning: Our Progressivist Inheritance from Herbert Spencer, John Dewey, and Jean Piaget. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Feigl, Herbert . ( 1949 ). “Logical Empiricism: Positivism, Not Negativism.” In Readings in Philosophical Analysis , ed. Herbert Feigl and Wilfred Sellars (pp. 3–25). New York: Appleton‐Century‐Crofts.

—— and Wilfred Sellars , eds. ( 1949 ). Readings in Philosophical Analysis . New York: Appleton‐Century‐Crofts.

Garrison, Jim , and Alven Neiman . ( 2003 ). “Pragmatism and Education.” In The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Education , ed. Nigel Blake , Paul Smeyers , Richard Smith , and Paul Standish (pp. 21–37). Oxford: Blackwell.

Gouinlock, James . ( 1986 ). Excellence in Public Discourse: John Stuart Mill, John Dewey, and Social Intelligence. New York: Teachers College Press.

Haack, Susan . ( 1993 ). Evidence and Inquiry: Towards Reconstruction in Epistemology. Oxford: Blackwell.

—— ( 1996 ). “Pragmatism.” In The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy , ed. N. Bunnin and E. P. Tsui‐James (pp. 643–61). Oxford: Blackwell.

Held, David . ( 1987 ). Models of Democracy. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Holmes, Oliver W. ( 1881 ). The Common Law. Boston: Little, Brown.

James, William . ( 1890 /1983). The Principles of Psychology . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. 10.1037/10538-000

—— ( 1901 /1983). Talks to Teachers on Psychology and to Students on Some of Life's Ideals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Incorporates the 1899 work Talks to Teachers on Psychology .)

—— ( 1907 ). Pragmatism , ed. F. Burkhardt and F. Bowers . Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Kloesel, Christian J. W. , ed. ( 1986 ). Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition, Vol. 3, 1872–1978. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

Lipman, Matthew . ( 2003 ). Thinking in Education , 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Llewellyn, Karl . ( 1930 ). “ A Realistic Jurisprudence—The Next Step. ” Columbia Law Review 30: 431–65. 10.2307/1114548

McAvoy, Paula . ( 2008 ). “ Should Arranged Marriages for Teenage Girls be Allowed? How Public Schools Should Respond to Illiberal Cultural Practices. ” Theory and Research in Education 6(1): 5–20. 10.1177/1477878507086728

Migotti, M. ( 1988 ). “ Recent Work in Pragmatism: Revolution or Reform in the Theory of Knowledge? ” Philosophical Books 29: 65–73. 10.1111/j.1468-0149.1988.tb02012.x

Mounce, H. O. ( 1997 ). The Two Pragmatisms: From Peirce to Rorty. London: Routledge.

Neiman, Alven . ( 1995 ). “Pragmatism: The Aims of Education and the Meaning of Life.” In Critical Conversations in Philosophy of Education , ed. W. Kohli (pp. 56–72). New York: Routledge.

Peirce, Charles . ( 1905 ). “ What Pragmatism Is. ” Monist 15(2): 161–81.

Pound, Roscoe . ( 1910 ). “ Law in Books and Law in Action. ” American Law Review 44: 12–36.

—— ( 1911 ). “ The Scope and Purpose of Sociological Jurisprudence. ” Harvard Law Review 24: 591–619. 10.2307/1324094

Power, F. Clark , Ann Higgins , and Lawrence Kohlberg . ( 1989 ). Lawrence Kohlberg's Approach to Moral Education. New York: Columbia University Press.

Putnam, Hilary . ( 1995 ). Pragmatism. Oxford: Blackwell.

Rorty, Richard . ( 1979 ). Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

—— ( 1991 ). Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Russell, Bertrand . ( 1905 ). “ On Denoting. ” Mind 14: 479–93.

Schmitter, Amy , Nathan Tarcov , and Wendy Donner . ( 2003 ). “Enlightenment Liberalism.” In A Companion to the Philosophy of Education , ed. Randall Curren (pp. 73–93). Oxford: Blackwell.

Slavin, Robert . ( 1995 ). Cooperative Learning: Theory, Research, and Practice , 2nd ed. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.

Standish, Paul . ( 2003 ). “The Nature and Purposes of Education.” In A Companion to the Philosophy of Education , ed. Randall Curren (pp. 221–31). Oxford: Blackwell.

Thayer, H. S. ( 1968 ). Meaning and Action: A Critical History of Pragmatism. New York: Bobbs‐Merrill.

Veblen, Thorstein .( 1899 ). The Theory of the Leisure Class. New York: Macmillan.

West, Cornel . ( 1989 ). The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

White, G. Edward . ( 1980 ). Tort Law in America . Oxford: Oxford University Press.

White, Morton . ( 1947 ). Social Thought in America: The Revolt against Formalism. Boston: Beacon Press.

Wiener, Philip P. ( 1949 ). Evolution and the Founders of Pragmatism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

—— ( 1973 ). “Pragmatism.” In Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Studies of Selected Pivotal Ideas , ed. P. Wiener (pp. 551–70). New York: Charles Scribner's Sons.

Zilversmit, Arthur . ( 1993 ). Changing Schools: Progressive Education Theory and Practice, 1930–1960 . Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Institutional account management
  • Rights and permissions
  • Get help with access
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

Pragmatism and Its Contribution to Education

Profile image of Dr Pratima Chamling Rai

As the word Pragmatic means the quality of dealing with the problem in a sensible way that suits the conditions that really exists, rather than following a fixed theories, ideas or rules. Pragmatism is an educational philosophy that says education should be teaching students the things that are practical for life and encourages them to grow into better people. Many famous educators including John Dewey, William James were pragmatists. Pragmatists believe in the idea of practical learning i.e. education should apply to the real world. Thus, this paper examines Pragmatism, its contribution to education. It further discusses how the basic principles of pragmatism can be applied in learning thereby making the process of teaching-learning more effective. Index Terms Learning, Method of Teaching, Pragmatism, Values

Related Papers

Rajendra Kumar Shah

In the field of pedagogical practices, two aspects have been studied with great interest. Educators have long been researching how to make classroom delivery effective in the 21st century. In this context, the difference between LCT and TCT has been studied for the long time. Some scholars have emphasized on TCT while many other scholars educators have emphasized on LCT. TCT is a very old and prevalent teaching and learning method. This method has its own advantages and disadvantages. Due to this reason this method is still prevalent today and many classrooms are being used unhindered. But philosophers such as Rousseau, Pestalozzi, Froebel, and Dewy have criticized TCT and advocated for LCT. Now, it is important to be clear about the difference between LCT and TCT. This study also attempts to clarify the differences between the two teaching methods. This article is prepared on the basis of in-depth study of various articles, research reports, books, various levels theses, etc. publi...

essay on pragmatism in education pdf

Anisha Tamang

Stress is a summation of effects on all non-specific biological experience extracted by difficulty and unpleasant exterior pleasures. One can feel it when he/she is confronted with a difficult and unavoidable situation. Stress in teaching profession restraints the quality of the teachers and the same creates a misery in the minds of the teachers due to heavy workload, multiple roles, changes in educational policy, inspection regime, continous professional growth and demands and high expectations from the teacher. Hence this study is performed to understand the factors causing stress among teachers and its effects on the education system, health and quality of life and thereby providing some suggestive measures for stress management. Teaching is a noble, prestigious and a responsible profession where the life and future of the students is dependent upon the performance of the teacher. Therefore, the teachers are the most valued assets of the country. They need to be competent as well...

Although learner centred teaching has recently beco me ne of the most prevalent educational ideas, the term LCT has long been in existence in the education setting . LCT is a very important teaching-learning process in the field of education. Studies and research are being done i n this regard all over the world. Teachers have a v ery important role to play in LCT. In addition, parents seem to h ave a very important role to play in LCT. But in LC T, teachers, students, parents, headmaster, family and society h ave a very important role to play. In this context, this study analyzes the role of teachers, students, parents an d educational materials in LCT. The IDR method has been used in this study. On the basis of the IDR, the role of teachers, students, parents and educational materi als in LCT has been analyzed. This study includes various research ticles, reports and dissertation published onlin e i the different countries of the World. Results of the pr sent study indicated that ...

The learner centered teaching LCT is a very important teaching and learning strategies in the field of education. LCT has been widely used in the literature around world. LCT is said to be one of the multiple labels of constructivist teaching philosophy. The focus of the instruction is to facilitate students to develop critical perspectives about the socio-economic, cultural, and political aspects. Developing critical thoughts amongst students, teachers need to cultivate a fluid relationship with their students such that students democratically and critically use their prior knowledge and experiences to build new conceptions of the topics. This method emphasizes on construction of knowledge rather than transformation of knowledge. Therefore, a number of pedagogical practices are closely associated with this teaching learning strategies. The major aim of this article to anlyze the relational instructional practices of LCT. On the basis of, various research articles, dissertations, re...

Dhanaji Thore

Francis Bacon’s “Essays” is a pearl of universal philosophy. They teach us those perpetual ethical doctrines which everyone must be acquainted with obligatory. He teaches worldly success for the overall development of human mind. It is undoubtedly a functional intelligence and it for sure contains a negotiation between ethics and worldly achievement. Bacon satisfies the person not critically to say about its antecedent, not because of extraordinary consciences, but because of the circumstance that the person does not monitor council would agonize with hostile values. From the elucidation it is imperious to resist that the very transformative excellence in Bacon&#39;s philosophy which is orientation similarly disfigured his objective. Though, the dominant impression or influences for his method were well rationalized by him but this is not to say that there were no defects in them. In fact, the very technique supported by him is itself challenging. Earliest Indian philosophy assumed ...

IJCRT - International Journal of Creative Research Though

Dr. Vijayapal Pathloth

The purpose of the paper is to emphasize Dance as a mode of healing. Since ages, Dance has been helpful to us in various capacities. Since ancient times it is used as a medium of communication, entertainment, spirituality – as an offering to Gods and so on. Dance, since its origin has undergone many developments and today, its knowledge is imparted in academics at various levels ranging from Certificate programmees to PhD programmee. Individuals are opting and practicing Dance either as profession or as a hobby and various other options. Today, in the contemporary era, Dance is viewed and treated differently as it has various other benefits. One among them is the healing capabilities. With the ingenious thoughts of Marian Chace – The grand Dame of Dance Therapy, Dance is witnessed as a medium of Therapy besides communication and entertainment. Me, being an Indian origin, and practicing Dance since more than 3 decades, would like to correlate the origin of Dance in general to the origin of Dance Therapy in particular, according to Indian mythology. According to Hindu mythology, Dance has been created by Lord Brahma to heal the illness (bad deeds, misery, jealousy, exploitation etc) of the humans on the earth and bring them back to a systematic life. Hence, I feel the reason for the origin of Dance itself is with a therapeutic motive. It clearly justifies that practicing and implementing Dance has various other benefits besides entertainment. Dance has always been as a means of communication and entertainment till nineteenth century. Subsequently, Dance is being perceived and viewed into various other means and approaches to spread its wings and branches. Dance is analysed, substantiated and proved into various disciplines and forms to manifest its efficiency besides entertainment. In this context, Dance is witnessed as a mode of Therapy from 1920 onwards by Marian Chace, the lady behind the concept of Dance Therapy. The present paper is a modest attempt to highlight the importance of Dance; and to bring in and establish the concept of Dance Therapy, its origin and evolution, while enlightening its significance.

International Journal of Creative Research Thoughts (IJCRT)

Studies on beliefs dates back to the field of psychology in the early 1900s. After the 1920s, however, interest in beliefs waned. It was not until the 1960s with the work of some psychologists such as Rokeach that the subject was revisited. In the 1970s, the inception of cognitive science opened the door to further pursuits of beliefs research. A transformation in the focus of education research began at this time. Heretofore, the focus had included only a behavioral emphasis wherein teachers' intentions were largely ignored. But the development of cognitive science provided a venue for education researchers to give increased attention to teacher cognition. This focus involves teacher thinking, including teacher beliefs. This development catapulted the study of beliefs in the 1980s in a variety of fields, including education. The major aim of the present study is to explore the concept, meaning and definition of the teachers' belief. Secondary sources such as internet, online resources, journal articles, thesis, and dissertation have been utilized to prepare this article. Accordingly, a specific literature search strategy was used in the present study. For this purpose, a literary search and selection of the related studies focusing on the teachers' belief generated mainly two types of studies-the qualitative and the quantitative type of studies. I searched scholarly and online databases (Google Scholar, JStor, Proquest) for studies published between 1950 to till the date that focus on the teachers' belief and related policies, trends, and issues in various countries. Results of the present study shows that it is very difficult to define teachers' belief and teachers' beliefs are an intangible construct' as they are made up of rational ideas developed over a period of time, through experiences gained while trying to understand a students' mind, and monitoring classroom behavior how students react to lectures. As a mental construct, beliefs are not easily defined, and indeed most scholars come to the consensus that beliefs are notoriously difficult to define. Accordingly there is difference among belief, knowledge and attitudes and teachers' belief is developed on the basis of personal experiences; experiences with schooling and instruction; and experience with formal Knowledge. Anthropologists, social psychologists, and philosophers have contributed to an understanding of the nature of beliefs and their effects on actions. There is considerable congruence of definition among these three disciplines in that beliefs are thought of as psychologically-held understandings, premises or propositions about the world that are felt to be true.

Dr.Rajkumar Nayak

Study of concept formation of learning disabled secondary students is the "Title" of the study. To study the Levels and differences in the concept formation of learning disabled students and normal students are the objectives of the study. The sample of the study consists of 2000 (two thousand) secondary school students. Out of which 1752 are normal students and 248 are Learning disabled students. Check list for identifying learning disabled students, Social Economic Test

The present study is carried out in order to analyze the existing Masters' Degree curriculum of Foundation of Education (ED 511). Descriptive survey design has been used in present study. 10 teachers of different college of Tribhuvan University and 20 post-graduation (M ED) students who studying at Sanothimi campus were selected as samples using purposive sampling methods. Results reveals that sufficient indigenous knowledge related contents are not instrumented in the existing curriculum of ED 511. Similarly, the results of the present study reveals that although the major general and specific objectives, contents, pedagogical activities and assessment procedures are satisfactory, sufficient indigenous knowledge friendly objectives and contents are not incorporated in the ED 511 curriculum. Only one topic related to indigenous knowledge is instrumented in the curriculum. Accordingly, general, specific objectives and assessment procedures cover some indigenous knowledge friendly contents. These provisions are not sufficient form the perspectives of indigenous knowledge. Similarly, indigenous knowledge that exists in society has historically been ignored and neglected. So, a majority of the respondents agreed that there is sufficient room for indigenous knowledge in the existing curriculum that could be incorporated in the Foundation of Education curriculum (ED 511). In this context, explicit and tacit indigenous knowledge could be instrumented in the existing ED. 511 curriculum easily. Accordingly, specific pedagogical practices and assessment procedure should be added for the effective implementation of these contents. Thus, it can be concluded that existing syllabus of ED 511 should be improved as per the norms of the changed need of the society and indigenous knowledge perspectives.

Dr. K . Arockiaraj

Inclusive development has gained ample emphasize in the education, employment and health sector. There have been enormous studies propagating the need for inclusiveness in education, employment and health. Most of the employability reports in India revealed that the present generation lack in employability and life skills. However, in most cases, equity fails in teaching and assessment. In such cases, most education systems have failed to include these skills integrated into curriculum, taught and evaluated. Boud and Falchikov (2010) suggest moving away from traditional way of teaching and assessment, which undermines students’ capacity to judge their own work, to authentic, work- or research- relevant assessments that better prepare students for future employability and coping with life. The intellectual capacity gains more space during the course of school life and no space for employability and life skills enhancement. This paper proves the need for integrating the employability/life skills into school curriculum and the academic performance evaluation should also include the employability/life skills. The opinion of 120 respondents (employers, teachers, parents and students) have been consolidated and described. Descriptive design has been used to describe the variables. SPSS software was used to process and infer the data. The findings and suggestion of this paper will pave way for emphasizing and strategizing the need for integrating and grading the employability/life skills of students.

RELATED PAPERS

Shadrack Ogoma

Pooja Walia

Dr.Drs. Achmad Noor Fatirul, ST., M.Pd.

shagufta N A Z N E E N ansari

Shalini rao

INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF CREATIVE RESEARCH THOUGHTS - IJCRT (IJCRT.ORG)

Nuruddin Ahmed Masud , Taherun Nesa Suborna

Sushmitha Gutti

Bokang Tantu

sheetla prasad

MARIMUTHU KN

Kenneth Nteh

Systems Research and Behavioural Science

Richard Ormerod

International Journal of Creative Research Thoughts

Sourovi Thakur

Paper Published at International Journal of Creative Research Thoughts

Dr. Neena Dash

Roel Juevesa

Dr.Rajkumar Nayak , Rajesh Kumar

Gissa Mahende

International Journal of Creative Research Thought

Dr. Arnab Kundu

NARESH RAMAVATH

Jankel Pahuyo

Dr. Mikael Chuaungo

Naushad Husain

Ali Ibrahim

Latha Mayan

Dr.Lallianzuali Fanai

INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF CREATIVE RESEARCH THOUGHTS - IJCRT

Biswajit Satpathy

S LELIAL MBAGATHEI

Sathyamurthi Karibeeran

Bahati Mfungo

Anupama Gadiraju

Prof. Ajay Kumar Attri

Urvi Sharma

vijaymohan das

Santwana Chaudhuri

abdulmumini inda

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

IMAGES

  1. The Pragmatic Education Philosophy

    essay on pragmatism in education pdf

  2. Pragmatism and Education: Download DSSSB PRT Study Notes

    essay on pragmatism in education pdf

  3. (PDF) Implementing Pragmatism And John Deweys Educational Philosophy In

    essay on pragmatism in education pdf

  4. pragmatism compress.pdf

    essay on pragmatism in education pdf

  5. PHILOSOPHY OF PRAGMATISM & EDUCATION

    essay on pragmatism in education pdf

  6. (PDF) Pragmatism in Education

    essay on pragmatism in education pdf

VIDEO

  1. Pragmatism #education #philosophy #western

  2. What is Pragmatism? Sociology Optional

  3. Pragmatism B.Ed 2nd Yr. knowledge and Curriculum

  4. What is pragmatism? #researchmethods #research #shorts #shortvideo #learning #philosophy

  5. Pragmatism

  6. Pragmatism

COMMENTS

  1. (PDF) Pragmatism in Education

    final or u ltimate truth. In other word, pragmatism is the philosophy that encourages us to seek out the. processes and do things that work best to help us achi eve desirable ends (Ozmon and ...

  2. PDF Pragmatism and Its Contribution to Education

    The teaching methods are based on learning by doing. The project method is the contribution of pragmatism to modern education. Pragmatism encourages a democratic way to learning through purposeful and co-operative projects and activities. Utility in the educative process is the first criterion.

  3. PDF Pragmatism and Its Implications on Teaching and Learning in ...

    Influence of Pragmatism on Teaching and Learning Pragmatists generally believe that experience is the source of all knowledge. In the same way, they define education in terms of experience. Education comes as a result of experience, it is a lesson learnt from experience. But it is not every experience that is education.

  4. (PDF) PRAGMATISM: ITS IMPLICATION TO EDUCATION 1

    Pragmatism is a. philosophy that encourages us to seek out the processes and do the things that work best to. help us achieve desirable ends. Pragma tism is primarily an American philosophy ...

  5. [PDF] Pragmatism in education

    Published 1 March 1968. Philosophy, Education. Studies in Philosophy and Education. When applied to problems in teaching philosophy, pragmatism improves philosophical teaching. It does so by deflating and clarifying the meaning of its problems and providing ways to understand and evaluate their effects on students and teachers.

  6. (PDF) Pragmatism in Philosophy of Education: A Contemporary Outlook

    In other word, pragmatism is the philosophy that encourages us to seek out the processes and do things that work best to help us achieve desirable ends (Ozmon and Craver, 2008). Pragmatism is also a practical, matter-of-fact way of approaching or assessing situations or of solving problems.

  7. Pragmatism in Education: Philosophical Foundations and Pedagogical

    The subject of this article is the ideas in the field of philosophy and practice of education, proposed by the founders of pragmatism: C. Pierce, W. James, J. Dewey, R. Rorty.

  8. Pragmatism and Education

    Pragmatism and Education Matthew Pamental Daniel Tröhler and Jürgen Oelkers, Eds. Pragmatism and Educationy Rotter-dam, The Netherlands: Sense Publishers, 2005. 236 pp. ISBN 9077874658 1 978- ... essay by comparing Mead s and Dewey's approaches and then noting several more specific implications for contemporary theory of schooling. Oelkers ...

  9. (PDF) The Significance of Pragmatism in Educational Research: A Current

    Data was derived from secondary sources comprising books, journals, scholarly papers and the internet. The expository and evaluative methods are employed for analysis. This study discovered that pragmatism has produced a distinctive epistemological outlook: a fallibilist, anti-Cartesian explication of the norms that govern inquiry.

  10. Educational Theory, Practice, and Research: Pragmatic ...

    To take a 'pragmatic' approach is, in ordinary language, to eschew lofty theory, ideology, and even rarefied scientific claims which, however researched, conflict with common-sense understanding. To take a pragmatic approach is try out a course of action against our own ordinary experience and to see if it 'works'.

  11. PDF John Dewey's Pragmatism: Implications for Reflection in Service ...

    Service-learning theory and practice often elides over or ignores entirely the principles of inquiry as developed by Dewey. The exercise of reflective thought requires that educators create a situation of dis-comfort for learners, and mandates that students examine the warrants of settled belief (i.e., assumptions).

  12. 26 Pragmatist Philosophy of Education

    Pragmatist philosophy and analytic philosophy are not fully disjoint forms of philosophy. There are, and have long been, analytic pragmatists, beginning with Charles Sanders Peirce (1839-1914), the founder of pragmatism and preeminent logician of his day, and analytic neo‐pragmatists, including Hilary Putnam (), Susan Haack (), and Robert Brandom (1994, 2000).

  13. [PDF] Pragmatism in Philosophy of Education: A Contemporary Outlook

    Pragmatism in Philosophy of Education: A Contemporary Outlook. Various schools of thought and philosophical systems have originated in philosophy in the course of time. One popular philosophy in the modern period is pragmatism. The core pragmatic maxim consists in a rule for clarifying the meaning of hypotheses by tracing their ̳practical ...

  14. [PDF] Pragmatism and Education

    Pragmatism and Education. In 1908, the Third International Congress of Philosophy convened in Heidelberg, Germany. According to the editors of Pragmatism and Education, this event witnessed a rejection of pragmatic ideas in Germany which would hold throughout most of the twentieth Century. In the wake of the American revival of pragmatism, the ...

  15. Pragmatism and Education

    Pragmatism and Education. Jim Garrison, Jim Garrison. Search for more papers by this author. Alven Neiman, Alven Neiman. Search for more papers by this author. Jim Garrison, Jim Garrison. ... View the article/chapter PDF and any associated supplements and figures for a period of 48 hours.

  16. (PDF) Pragmatism in Education

    According to pragmatism the theory and practice of education is based on two main principles, viz: (i) Education should have a social function, and (ii) Education should provide real-life experience to the child. Various schools of thought and philosophical systems have originated in philosophy in the course of time.

  17. (PDF) The Utility of Pragmatism in Educational Research

    This essay traces the evolution of the pragmatist elements in Wiggins's distinctive view of truth and shows its connections to the founder of pragmatism, C.S. Peirce and one of Peirce's greatest ...

  18. (PDF) Pragmatism and education

    PDF | On Mar 25, 2016, Mahdieh Hosseini published Pragmatism and education | Find, read and cite all the research you need on ResearchGate

  19. (PDF) Pragmatism, Education, and Children

    Pragmatism, Education, and Children: International Philosophical Perspectives, edited by Michael Taylor, Helmut Schreier, and Paulo Ghiraldelli, Jr. Amsterdam and New York: Rodopi, 2008. 248 pages. This book, a volume in the Value Inquiry Book Series and also in Studies in Pragmatism and Values, covers a wide range of pragmatic approaches to ...

  20. (PDF) Education Philosophy of Pragmatism and its Impact in the Global

    This essay examines the provenance of a single, curious term that William James often used in connection with his own pragmatism. The term is Denkmittel , an uncommon German contraction of Denk ...

  21. (PDF) Pragmatism-Philosophy of John Dewey's Education: Role and

    Pragmatism has had a huge impact on education, and that will also be covered in great detail. At the end of the paper, we will compare pragmatism to other influential philosophical principles such as naturalism and idealism, which will then be followed by the conclusion. Keywords: pragmatism, education, philosophical principles.

  22. (PDF) Pragmatism and Education

    Jackson begins his essay with an exploration of ten concepts he believes hold the key to Dewey's optimism. E&C Education and Culture Review: Pragmatism and Education ฀฀85 He then considers briefly what those themes have in common. In particular, Jackson makes three observations.

  23. Pragmatism and Its Contribution to Education

    According to Pragmatism, education is not the dynamic side of philosophy as advocated by the idealists. It is the philosophy which emerges from an educational practice. Every individual has a social self and he can be best developed in and through society. Thus, we can conclude by saying that that Pragmatism has brought democracy in education.